Printer Friendly

THE GREAT RIFT: Literacy, Numeracy, and the Religion-Science Divide.

THE GREAT RIFT: Literacy, Numeracy, and the Religion-Science Divide by Michael E. Hobart. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2018. xiv + 506 pages, with appendices, endnotes, and index. Hardcover; $39.95. ISBN: 9780674983632.

Michael Hobart's book The Great Rift presents a novel and provocative perspective on the age-old conflict between religion and science. In his words:
My central thesis may be baldly and succinctly stated: the shift
between two distinct information technologies--literacy and
numeracy--resides at the source of how science and religion went their
separate ways, producing the Great Rift between them. (p. 4)


To be clear, Hobart does not specifically address the alleged discord between science and religion but delineates how a chasm (his word) opened up to drive them apart. Nevertheless, Hobart holds that as life became ever more secularized, religion became less relevant to science and was "not so much conquered as ignored" (p. 10), so that "from the late nineteenth century to our own times we have reached the point where observers and participants alike... have come to view the widening separation between science and religion as an impasse, or even a war zone" (p. 323).

To support his thesis, Hobart fleshes out and refines some research begun two decades earlier with a colleague on transitions between the three stages in the history of information technology: literacy, numeracy, and computerized information processing. The result here is a well-researched book, based on a lifetime of work, that extensively examines medieval and Renaissance developments in mathematics as well as Galileo's seminal role in the rise of modern science. The detailed scholarly treatment given these topics, which we cannot adequately recapitulate here, makes the book well worth its modest price, completely aside from its take on the science-religion divide.

Hobart begins his narrative with a brief look at the ancient world, which introduced and developed the information technology of recorded language. Greek writing is epitomized by its literature and philosophy, which make extensive use of definition and classification to capture the essence of things. Aristotle systematically codified forms of deductive reasoning based on this type of thinking in his logic. Medieval schoolmen later adopted this mode of knowledge acquisition in their educational practices and intellectual debates. Classification and fine distinctions permeated the writings of those who studied the quadrivium (arithmetic, music, geometry, and astronomy) as well as the writings of those dedicated to more advanced topics in theology and philosophy.

During this time period, there was a methodological unity overall to science and religion. Thinkers described the observed behavior of natural phenomena in terms of causes related to their essential natures, leaving room for divine purposes at the head of it all. They employed the same sort of reasoning that explained the structure of the natural world to incorporate religious ends and means. Science and religion in medieval Europe formed a fairly harmonious whole.

As people began to use mathematics more consistently in the late Middle Ages and Renaissance in order to relate things in everyday arenas such as commercial transactions, music, perspective painting, and astronomy, the explanatory focus for natural phenomena moved away from appealing to the intrinsic nature of things to demonstrating how they functioned quantitatively. Mathematically relating numerical features of events or activities via ratio and proportion (the rule of three was an omnipresent mainstay) became the new mode of accounting for natural phenomena. This approach was fruitfully employed by Galileo in his scientific analysis of terrestrial motion, yielding his times-squared law for falling bodies and parabolic paths for projectiles. Such an approach left both traditional philosophy and theology on the outside, creating a fault line between science and religion. Galileo's clash with the Roman Catholic Church over the factual status of Copernican astronomy, the nature of scientific demonstration, and the legitimacy of theological incursions into science only exacerbated this rift.

Hobart attributes the new analytic approach in natural philosophy to changes in information technology, indeed, to the rise of numeracy. He sees developments within mixed/applied mathematics during the Renaissance and early modern period as embodying a new understanding of the nature of mathematics and the role of symbols. Using terms proposed in 1959 by Jagjit Singh (but for distinguishing formalistic late nineteenth- and twentieth-century mathematics from its more concrete antecedents), Hobart brands classical and medieval mathematics as "thing mathematics" and Renaissance and early modern mathematics as "relation mathematics." This characterization works to some extent, but it has shortcomings.

Classical mathematics was certainly about mathematical entities encountered in everyday life (numbers, spatial figures), but it also treated their basic properties (being prime, being isosceles) and relations (being divisible by, being congruent to). Hobart correctly notes that late medieval, Renaissance, and early modern mathematics made extensive and productive use of relations such as ratio and proportion (a significant part of what qualifies them as being relation mathematics) to formulate functional dependencies, but these relations were also prominent in earlier mathematics--in the works of Euclid, Archimedes, Apollonius, Heron, and Ptolemy, and even in the mathematical practice of earlier cultures.

Another aspect of the new relation mathematics, as Hobart conceptualizes it, is an emphasis on the use of abstract or empty symbols. In one sense, this was not new. As far back as the end of the third millennium BC, for instance, the Mesopotamian sexagesimal place-value system made abstract computations possible, so that the differing concrete metrological systems still in use could be bypassed. But, in another sense, applying this characterization to late medieval, Renaissance, and early modern mathematics is anachronistic. Hindu-Arabic numerals referred to quantities such as goods, weights, and monetary value in commercial arithmetics; musical notation denoted temporal duration, pitch relations, harmonies, and time signatures; and letters used in the analysis of motion stood for speeds, times, and distances. More-abstract symbols were introduced in algebra by Viete and others to stand for numerical operations as well as unknown and known quantities, and these were used to formulate and solve equations, but they were not vacuous--they had numerical meaning in some assumed domain of quantities. Furthermore, while Viete made some major notational advances in algebra for solving equations prior to 1600, Galileo remained rooted in an older geometric form of ratio arithmetic that he learned from the recently recovered Book V of Euclid's Elements. In his earlier work, Hobart highlighted Viete's role in the new numeracy, but here Galileo is his protagonist. Galileo does use mathematical symbolism to analyze relations among physical quantities, but these are neither empty of meaning nor related by equations.

However, there is some validity to Hobart's assertion that the symbols of modern relation mathematics were becoming empty. As mathematics was increasingly being used to quantify empirical realities such as cost, distance, harmony, time, speed, and so on, time-worn metaphysical and occult connotations of numbers and spatial configurations became superfluous, and, as a result, symbolic representations were emptied of enchanted meaning. This practice became more widespread as time went on, though as Hobart acknowledges, it was not uniformly followed even by the start of the 1600s. Mystical associations of mathematics were often deemed as important as practical applications; in fact, this development encouraged some to believe that mathematics would unravel the secrets of nature. Kepler's astronomical writing, for example, contains hard-nosed calculations about elliptic planetary orbits and also religious and mystical ruminations about Platonic solids and the ability to think God's thoughts after him.

More could be said about Hobart's defense of his thesis--particularly his idiosyncratic use of the notions of cardinality and ordinality in connection with mathematicians beginning to join the fields of number and space in their practice of mixed mathematics--but I will end with a question and follow that with a few concluding remarks.

What is gained, I wonder, by conceptualizing the transformation of natural philosophy (from using Aristotelian teleological argumentation to employing mathematical analyses of functional dependencies) as a sweeping shift in information technology, exchanging words for empty quantitative symbolism? Why is this not seen instead, for instance, as a renewed neo-Pythagorean/Archimedean emphasis on the primacy of quantifying (mathematization) combined with a more experimental and mechanistic bent in physical investigations? That is, why concentrate so exclusively on the how of information technology--"the humanly constructed screen between the knowing mind and the world outside" (p. x)--rather than on the what of the discovered numerical connections between meaningful content? Hobart would no doubt respond that the latter does not occur without the former and that his stated aim is to determine the extent to which a change in information technology is implicated in the new mode of doing science, but I think more could have been done with developments on the religion and philosophy side of the divide to contextualize the shift.

Hobart successfully documents the changing methodology of science in the early modern period, especially in his expert examination of Galileo's work, but his thesis does not account for other important issues concerning the relationship of science and religion, even in this time period. I remain convinced that much more than information technologies are involved in the rise of modern science and its connection to religion. To be fair, some of these factors are acknowledged in passing by Hobart. He admits that changing attitudes toward the roles of religion and philosophy in the pursuit of natural knowledge were influenced by historical developments such as the rise of nominalism, the Reformation, Renaissance humanism, the revival of Platonism, gradual secularization, and so on, but these lie mostly outside the scope of his thesis. More importantly, Hobart does not probe the significant ways that Christian religion--in both its medieval and early modern versions--provided a hospitable intellectual environment in which modern science could develop and thrive, Galileo's conflict with the church notwithstanding. Readers who recognize God as the author of nature (and of creation more broadly) will not be persuaded by Hobart's allegation that "the deep incompatibility of religion and science" is now "simply too great to overcome" (p. 323). Distinct epistemic methodologies or information technologies do not automatically create territorial conflicts, and what discord there is, can often be attributed to other factors, such as the opposition between Christian faith and a strong commitment to naturalism.

Reviewed by Calvin Jongsma, Professor of Mathematics Emeritus, Dordt College, Sioux Center, IA 51250.
COPYRIGHT 2019 American Scientific Affiliation
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2019 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Title Annotation:HISTORY OF SCIENCE
Author:Jongsma, Calvin
Publication:Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith
Article Type:Book review
Date:Jun 1, 2019
Words:1699
Previous Article:DARWIN'S FIRST THEORY: Exploring Darwin's Quest to Find a Theory of Earth.
Next Article:KNOWING CREATION: Perspectives from Theology, Philosophy, and Science.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2019 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters