Printer Friendly

Response to Hartmann on political economy.

1. Introduction

At one time, it was rare that a major media personality published a major thought piece on political economy. In times of yore, mainstream radio and television hosts would for the most part limit themselves to reading the news and interviewing those who themselves made it. (1) In the modern era, however, it is not at all unusual to see talk show hosts go far beyond this role, and take up that of the political economist. (2) While Hartmann (2004) is not a full length treatment on economics and politics, it is substantial enough to call forth a rejoinder. And, it is important that this be done, (3) for it not at all represents the thinking of just this one author and high profile media commentator; (4) rather, it is fair to say, there are a substantial number of those who characterize themselves as "progressives," or "liberals," or "democrats," or "socialists," who would subscribe to these doctrines. Certainly, considerations articulated by Hartmann (2004) inform the thinking of other left wing commentators such as Keith Olbermann, (5) as well as President Barack Obama and his leading advisors.

Hartmann (2004) advances two major and related claims. First, he claims that there is no such thing as a free market, and second, that the middle class exists only because of government intervention. As we shall see, both of these claims are fatally flawed, as well as are a whole host of other assertions, dealing with rules of the game, money supply, free trade, and unemployment.

In section II of this paper we deal with Hartmann's charge that the free market cannot exist. Section III is devoted to this author's views on stable currency and other government "contributions." The burden of section IV is an analysis of his claim that government should be the referee for the economy. In section V we take Hartmann to task for his views on the middle class and in section VI do the same regarding his claims concerning the political spectrum. We conclude in section VII.

2. No Free Market

We turn now to Hartmann's first claim, that there is no such thing as a free market. If Hartmann meant that there does not exist a free market today, we would agree wholeheartedly. After all, had there been any such thing in existence, there would be no housing and monetary crisis facing us, no unemployment, no misdirection of young people away from the labor market and into four years of extended adolescence. Further, virtually the entire value of our dollar would not have been inflated away, we would not be dealing with the Social Security Ponzi scheme, nor would we now be crushed by a mountain of debt. Clearly, the markets we see today are the products of decades, nay, centuries, of government interference. Alas, Hartmann rather means to say that there is no such thing as a free market even in principle, but that is preposterous. All that is needed for laissez faire capitalism is proper enforcement of just private property claims, and equitable courts for enforcement of proper contracts. Has this system ever been implemented perfectly? No, of course not, perfection is denied us on this side of the Garden of Eden. However, several countries, for many years, have approached this system, with highly benevolent results (Gwartney, 1976) the closer they have come to it. Hong Kong, Singapore and Switzerland have implemented free markets to the greatest degree of any countries in the modern era, and these nations have vibrant economies. West Germany and South Korea have come far closer to free enterprise than their counterparts in East Germany and North Korea, which had adopted economic rules more compatible with those ad vocated by Hartmann (2004). Yet, the latter country has been earmarked by literal starvation, and the voting with the feet of the Germans was strongly in the direction of the freer economy. We mention these two cases since they serve, almost, as laboratories for our topic: the people in each pair spoke the same language, had the same customs, the same educational levels; it was only due to an accident of war that they were rent asunder. Unhappily, Hartmann (2004) calls for more and more government regulations, controls and central economic direction, precisely the policies of East Germany and North Korea. That is "progressive?"

If there is no free market without a government, then how do we explain the massive failure of the government's own war on drugs? Somehow, despite the state's best efforts to the contrary, that market continues to thrive, innovate, and expand even in the face of government's active attempts to shut it down! If statist bureaucrats really are necessary for a market to function, how can a drug trade not only survive but flourish with government not just withdrawing support (which Hartmann deems necessary for any market) but also spending billions trying (and failing) to slow it down? The statists are so impotent in this regard that they cannot even stop drug markets within prisons, an environment totally under their control. And, this is only the tip of the iceberg. The same may be said of any government prohibition, where a black market arises to take up the slack. This applies, then, certainly, to alcohol during prohibition, to gambling (before legalization, and nationalization in form of lotteries), to prostitution, pornography, etc.

3. Stable Currency

According to Hartmann (2004): "Governments provide a stable currency to make markets possible. They provide a legal infrastructure and court systems to enforce the contracts that make markets possible. They provide educated workforces through public education, and those workers show up at their places of business after traveling on public roads, rails, or airways provided by government. Businesses that use the 'free market' are protected by police and fire departments provided by government, and send their communications from phone to fax to internet--over lines that follow public rights-of-way maintained and protected by government."

This is highly problematic. Where are these stable currencies that governments provide? The claim that government provides a "stable" currency is undermined by the fact that the dollar has fallen in value by over 97% since the Federal Reserve system was created in 1913, (6) in the name of "price stability." How can something fall by 97% (with much more to come, especially given QE2, the bailouts, etc) and be considered "stable?" The U.S. experience in the last 100 years is only the tip of the iceberg in refuting this claim of Hartmann's. It was not for nothing that the U.S. government in the early days of our country so debauched the currency that the phrase was born, "Not worth a Continental," the currency of the day. And, to take a more international perspective, the hyperinflations of Germany in 1923, South America a decade ago, and Zimbabwe in the present day, add more counter examples to the unwarranted claim that "government" and "stable currency" should be even mentioned in the same sentence. If mere printing up of money could bring prosperity, then every nation would be rich, since they all have printing presses. (7)

Where are the courts that enforce contracts, rather than undermining them? (8) It is true that public education does something, but Gatto, among others, (9) has done great work in showing that what they provide has little or nothing to do with education. Of course, as these scholars point out, one purpose of public education is providing subservient workers and unthinking consumers, but does Hartmann really wish to have the government take credit for this? Is it supposed to be a triumph of statism that corporations are made wealthy at the expense of the poorly educated? If the government wishes to take credit for corporate oligarchy, we ought to allow them to do so. As far as the police departments are concerned, we notice that they do not respond to major thefts. Where were these police departments when billions upon billions were stolen and provided to criminals in banks and business? Where were the governmental police when half of our paychecks were stolen, mostly to provide for the killing of people with tan skin and long last names? Alas, they were supporting such theft, not acting against it.

More importantly, though, Hartmann entirely fails, in fact, does not even attempt, to offer an argument that government provision of these services is a good method, or the best one, to provide them. If one wishes to claim that even in principle, free markets cannot exist, because the existence of markets depends necessarily on government actions, then one would need to offer some reason that, in fact, the market itself cannot create the infrastructure credited to government. In fact, a market economy could, and, indeed, has, provided all of these services, including courts, police, law, education, a stable currency, tasks that have proven impossible for our masters in Washington D.C.. All the services listed by Hartmann are provided by government only because that institution itself claims a monopoly on them; that is, threatens to kill those who attempt to provide them in competition to itself. If this is supposed to prove that only government can provide these things, Hartmann would be advised to take a course in logic.

Hartmann, truth be told, is inadvertently correct in his claim that we should not say "the market" provides these goods and services. In fact, they are, instead, provided by entrepreneurs, that is, specific economic actors, in exchange for other items and valuable considerations. We have no need to presume that there is such a thing as "the market" which drops them into our lap, much as government does now. Instead, the infrastructure of market transactions is based upon the contributions of entrepreneurs.

What is more, government provides these things quite poorly. It does so in such a way as to disproportionately benefit large capital holders and powerful business owners, at the expense of other classes of people.10 For example, governments do not offer stable currencies, they provide unstable ones that wipe out the savers and benefit the banks. They do not supply courts and protective services that protect all equally; these services protect mainly the wealthiest. Public education locks poor students into the schools provided by their (poor) tax base, and bureaucrats choose the content and methods of education by the political process, rather than by allowing students to gravitate towards that which suits them best. The schools train students to be uncritical, to take orders from their superiors, to be unsure of their own abilities, and to consume voraciously. That is, the schools are biased in favor of the corporate fat cats, not the large populations that pay for them.

Hartmann (2004) makes the unjustified assumption that libertarians are wrong in their core belief that the non aggression principle trumps every other economic, political, or moral theory ever devised. Libertarians believe in non aggression; it is the only correct deontological theory, and the only practical one as well. (11)

Of course libertarians use public schools, public roads, and the "stable" US dollar almost every single day. There are several justifications for this. For one thing, what choice do we have? The government outlaws private, competing currencies and thus forces us to accept fiat money, if we wish to engage in the modern exchange economy, without which our lives would be "nasty, brutish and short," if we were able to remain alive at all. We are forced to pay for roads (via gas taxes) and schools (property taxes). If these public institutions were so exemplary, why wouldn't the government allow private businesses and individuals to compete with them, to really "prove" which type of institution is best? The government may be composed of a band of thugs and criminals (Spooner, 1870), but they are not entirely stupid. They know that given fair competition (for example, allow all funding of government roads, schools, etc., to be voluntary, not forced at gun point) the so called supposedly "mythical" free market would win every time. (12)

But there is more to the justification of libertarians availing themselves of public service than that. Given that the government is illegitimate in the first place, since it engages in initiatory force in violation of the libertarian non aggression principle, (13) taking from it, in the form of utilizing its services, takes on a very different cast. Instead of stealing from the rightful owner, such acts take on the role of liberating stolen property from the thief. (14)

4. Government as Referee

According to Hartmann (2004) the government also provides "the rules of the game of business." Now, although business is not a game, (15) it is certainly true that it needs rules. Luckily, the nature of economics itself provides precisely those regulations. Thus, businesses which pay too little to workers are unable to attract a sufficient labor force, those which provide a poor quality product quickly run out of customers and go bankrupt, and so on. Far from providing the rules of the game, the government has only one ability--to exempt certain individuals and firms from their economic regulations. Thus, businesses providing a poor product can ask government to exempt them from the rules of economics by outlawing their competition, or by simply transferring them resources in order to remain in operation; for example, the recent auto and bank bailouts. Managers who lower the value of their stocks then ask the government to prevent a takeover, which would cost them their job. Corporations that grow too large and begin to fall prey to inefficiencies resulting from calculation problems petition the government to keep them in business.

However, in Hartmann's world, such things don't happen. Here is a particularly ironic example:
   Markets are a creation of government, just as corporations exist
   only by authorization of government. Governments set the rules of
   the market. And, since our government is of, by, and for We The
   People, those rules have historically been set to first maximize
   the public good resulting from people doing business. If you want
   to play the game of business, we've said in the US since 1784 (when
   Tench Coxe got the first tariffs passed 'to protect domestic
   industries') then you have to play in a way that both makes you
   money AND serves the public interest.


Hartmann first claims that government, rather than protecting big business, sets the rules to maximize the public good--but then immediately cites tariffs as an example! However, tariffs are nothing more than coercive levies that benefit a particular industry at the expense of its own customers. Far from serving the public interest, such policies serve a narrow private interest at the expense of the larger public interest. They allow a business, rather than responding to demands of consumers, to ignore them since they will be denied the choice to receive their goods elsewhere.

Now, is there a way to ensure that businesses will act in the public interest, and be punished if they fail to? Certainly--so long as the rules of the game are provided by marketplace competition, this will be the case. All members of the public are represented, because they all participate in the market. On the other hand, not all can take part in the political process. Those who have the most capital call the shots, since they need only bribe (or lobby) one very and all too responsive organization. Far from serving the "public interest" we receive policies that, in fact, favor one interest over another, such as the very tariffs that Hartmann cites. (16)

Hartmann (2004) says sports such as football, baseball etc., would not work without rules. But does the government impose these rules on, say, the NFL? Of course not! The NFL updates and changes its rules based mainly on fan (customer) input! For example there may be a rule change to the overtime period to add more excitement because fans expressed an interest in that. So by trying to prove his argument (we "need" governments to provide order) the author instead refutes it with his own example! There is no Congressional panel looking into NFL holding penalties or NBA shot clock violations (at least not for now), and yet both leagues work just fine. Imagine that.

The author also claims that businesses "work" with government rules. Why the need for bailouts then? If the rules really did work, they would effectively stamp out any negative impact from "greedy" speculators before they threatened to bring down the entire world economy. Alas, those amazing government "rules" failed to stem the flow of money lost, and many firms were on the verge of collapse even with these vaunted "rules" firmly in place.

In fact, one might go so far as to say that the government is the major violator of law. What, after all, is the essence of law? Surely, it is to uphold private property rights, in ourselves and in physical objects, and to stop usurpations thereof. (17) Namely, the libertarian non aggression principle (NAP) is the basic premise of all legitimate legal systems. How does the state violate these rights? In a myriad of ways, ranging from telling us how large must be the water closets in our toilets, to forbidding us from ingesting certain drugs without its permission, to mandating the size of our step-ladders, to taxing us. (18)

5. The Middle Class

We turn now to Hartmann's second major claim, regarding the middle class. We might, indeed, wonder why this is worth arguing about. After all, what we should support in this context is economic liberty and free markets, not any particular distribution of wealth. If government creates the middle class, and it would not exist absent government interference, so much the worse for the middle class. This need not be a hard-hearted argument, either; in a free market world, the level of wealth creation would far exceed that of our present world (Gwartney, 1996). Indeed, the poorest might well be as rich as our richest today; need we concern ourselves, then, about relative levels of wealth when all would be better off than today? However, even this need not be granted. Government intervention increases, rather than decreases, inequality. (19) Thus, a free market world would tend towards a larger middle class, not a smaller one.

Here is Hartmann's claim about the middle class:
   When government sets the rules of the game of business in such a
   way that working people must receive a living wage, labor has the
   power to organize into unions just as capital can organize into
   corporations, and domestic industries are protected from overseas
   competition, a middle class will emerge. When government gives up
   these functions, the middle class vanishes and we return to the
   Dickens-era 'normal' form of totally free market conservative
   economics where the rich get richer while the working poor are kept
   in a constant state of fear and anxiety so the cost of their labor
   will always be cheap.


We might, first of all, justifiably ask what entitles Hartmann to be so provincial in his valuations. Even at first glance, his argument here falls apart entirely if we look at a global picture of the world, rather than just the people who are subject to any one particular government. To protect domestic industries from overseas protection, after all, is supposed to (by Hartmann's lights) enrich the domestic population at the expense of foreign labor--thus globally producing a shrunken middle class and a larger class of poor laborers. Feigning concern that a free market would produce elites, a small middle, and a large poor class, Hartmann then immediately proceeds to defend government intervention on the grounds that it provides, for citizens of one country, a group of poor laborers abroad to serve them!

However, this is not the only class that Hartmann has ignored. What of consumers, who are forced to buy inferior products or simply to do without? What of laborers who are denied the ability to work for overseas companies --or does Hartmann expect foreign companies to offer jobs to a country that unilaterally outright forbids, or radically retards, trade? Even regarding the people Hartmann wishes us to look at, the benefit is illusory. Cutting off trade impoverishes the nation--this is why blockades are considered acts of war, not of charity--and hence even those supposedly helped by tariffs will, in time, suffer along with their nation.

Hartmann's claim here is that tariffs themselves are the way that governments protect the middle class. They are also the way that governments prevent greater economic growth. Trade, we have known since the days of yore of Smith and Ricardo, benefits all parties. By denying Americans the ability to trade, we impoverish, first, Americans, and second, the rest of the world. Hartmann's only defense is to invoke his apparent lack of knowledge of basic economics. If, per impossible, he understands the dismal science and yet persists in making these fallacious claims, he has much to answer for.

As for unionism making society richer, this, too, is a problematic claim. What makes us wealthy is producing more goods and services. So, the issue then becomes, How has organized labor acted historically? The fact is, far from fighting for equity for workers or enhancing output, unions have consistently stood in the way of progress. They have joined with government in reducing our standard of living by decreasing production, threatening violence against producers and supporting minimum wage laws. Dues paid by the rank and file have gone mostly to funding pro-corporate welfare politicians, in exchange for small concessions, rather than opposing unjust ownership or fighting for real changes that would help workers, such as an end to subsidies and corporate privilege. Due to the degree of economic illiteracy from which most Americans suffer, unions are able to behave in this manner and still be assumed by liberals, well-meaning and otherwise, to be a beneficial force. (20)

Further, unions have buttered the bread of thousands, if not hundreds of thousands of politicians at various local, state, and federal posts. As we can still see today, unionization as a saving grace for American workers and companies is nothing more than a pipe dream. One need not look much further than the United Auto Worker's union to see that. They basically milked GM and Chrysler for everything they could, including exorbitant pay rates, ridiculous benefits, etc and then came crying to Uncle Sam for a bailout when the spigot finally went dry. Talk about a nice, cozy relationship. Perhaps anything less than a hundred thousand a year to sit around and do crossword puzzles is considered "abuse" nowadays.

We do agree with Hartmann that Reagan and both Bushes were horrible drags on economic growth, liberty, and progress, not only for the middle class but for everyone. But this hardly helps Hartmann's critique of free enterprise, since if there is anything that these three presidents were not, it was champions of economic freedom. (21)

Hartmann (2004) says there is "no market independent of government" to which we reply "yes, and that is precisely the problem!" The statists have effectively elbowed their way into nearly every corner of our lives. And we are all worse off because of it. Let us again return to Hartmann (2004), "When government sets the rules of the game of business in such a way that working people must receive a living wage ..."

There are difficulties here. All too often the government does the exact opposite of this, subsidizing people who don't work (through unemployment insurance) and instituting a minimum wage that effectively outlaws those with poor skills from working. The author, and many other apologists for the state, takes it upon himself to decide what a "living wage" is, instead of simply letting workers and employers negotiate that on their own. This smacks of conceit, condescension and arbitrariness (Hayek, 1988). Yet another source of unemployment is the Fed's artificially lowering of interest rates, engendering vast misallocations of resources into earlier order goods such as mining, heavy industry, automobiles, housing construction, etc., which cannot be sustained and leads to an inevitable bust. (22)

To Hartmann, cheap labor is something to be avoided at all costs. We also must not trade "too much" with foreigners. But, what makes "Americans" as a group so special, compared to, say, Pennsylvanians? Floridians? Residents of your own county or street or even household? Should we not follow Hartmann's logic of "trade with outsiders ultimately is destructive" to its final, pitiful endgame? Why trade at all? The point is, if we in the U.S. "lose" via free trade with other countries, and they, presumably, from interacting, commercially, with us, then it would logically follow that when Pennsylvanians swap goods and services with Floridians, they both lose. Or, take two cities in any one state: (23) for example, Baton Rouge and New Orleans, both in Louisiana. Surely, according to the Hartmannian "logic," people in these two places should also refuse to have any commercial dealings with each other, lest they both suffer. It would be difficult to come up with a more economically illiterate proposition than this. No, the more options, the better price and deal we can all get.

How arrogant of the author to say something such as "bring American jobs back to America." How can jobs even belong to a country? This is the height of stupidity, empty logic, and plain rhetoric that is all too common in America. More "American jobs" is good for America. And less is bad. So why not outlaw all workers outside of the USA? After all, they are a potential "threat" to "dump cheap goods" on us. Or is it just the "good, high paying American jobs" that we need to protect? But then, what about the middle class Hartmann claims to vigorously support?

The difficulty, here, is that Hartmann has been taken in by the lump of labor fallacy: that there are only so many jobs to go around, and that if others, foreigners for example, get more of them, then there will only be fewer for us, and by that exact amount. However, the number of jobs is limited, only, by the fact that we want more things than we have; in a word, that there is scarcity. If there is one thing we can rely upon, however, it is that scarcity will always be with us. Therefore, the number of jobs still remaining to be done will always be indefinitely large. (24)

It is difficult to understand the author's almost creepy obsession with "America's Golden Middle Class." The notion that "labor" needs government to stand up for it against the big, bad corporations is hard to comprehend. The same group (government) that presided over legalized slavery and two world wars is now to be trusted to "protect" someone against a company that in essence pays all of the bills for the "abused" worked? Some sort of abuse that must be. Why would anyone continue to work for a company that routinely abuses him? Obviously the benefits (a paycheck chief among them) outweigh the costs (no electric, heat, water, food, shelter, tv, car etc) of working at said company or else the worker would simply seek alternative employment.

But perhaps Hartmann's most egregious howler with regard to the "middle class" is this:
   But, conservatives say, government is the problem, not the
   solution. Of course, they can't explain how it was that the
   repeated series of huge tax cuts for the wealthy by the Herbert
   Hoover administration brought us the Great Depression, while
   raising taxes to provide for an active and interventionist
   government to protect the rights of labor to organize throughout
   the 1930s, 1940s, and 1950s led us to the Golden Age of the
   American Middle Class.


In actual point of fact, both Hoover (25) and Roosevelt after him engaged in these New Deal Keynesian policies which boomeranged, and both exacerbated and prolonged the very depression they were meant to quell. In contrast, Warren G. Harding, a decade earlier, faced similar challenges (Woods, 2009), but did not tax and spend and intervene in the economy. The result? No depression at that time.

6. Political Spectrum

We should note that Hartmann's entire article relies on a false dichotomy being implicitly used: between "conservative economics" and "liberal economics." The former is supposed to indicate supporters of free markets, but includes advocacy for policies such as central banking and corporate welfare, as shown by Hartmann's inclusion of Hamilton and Adams in this group. So, in fact, the entire argument is flawed from the start--he has included under the "conservative" label two very different approaches to economic policy, and attempts to blame the harm done by one on the other. But we must set aside his false dichotomy and equivocation, and realize that there is all the world of difference between "conservative economics" on the one hand, and "libertarian economics" on the other. Many of this author's errors stem from the fact that the former is really more akin to state monopoly corporate capitalism, or fascism, while only the latter represents true economic freedom.

Conservatives do indeed sometimes say that "government is the problem, not the solution," while at the same time dragging us into trillion dollar war after trillion dollar war, pushing their morals on us with the help of the state apparatus, escalating the coercive war on drugs, etc, etc. While George Bush was a hero for conservatives, for libertarians he was evil. He helped push the bailouts down our throats, enhanced the role of the state in pharmaceuticals, and increased the government's role in the economy, both financially and via regulations. The philosophical gap between George Bush on the right, and Hartmann and Barack Obama on the left, is far smaller than that which lies between both of the sets of people, on the one hand, and libertarians on the other. This certainly holds true for public schools, roads, taxes, any and all government regulation, health and welfare.

According to Hartmann (2004): "Only a return to liberal economic policies --a return to We The People again setting and enforcing the rules of the game of business--will reverse this dangerous trend."

We would ask the author to choose between one of two living arrangements. He can either be a very well to do business man in 1890 (think Rockefeller or Carnegie) or a middle manager working for something around $50,000 per year (hardly rich, yet not poor, a member of the almighty "middle class" in 2011). Which would he choose? Remember, in the earlier period there is no Internet, no cell phone or iPod (or iPad), no personal computer, no Blackberry, no high definition television, a much more limited selection at the grocery store, far fewer restaurants to say nothing of advances in medicine, dentistry, transportation, etc. We could go on practically forever about the advancements and improvements since just the late 1800s. So where is this "dangerous trend" Hartmann speaks of? Surely, we are raising the living standards at least in that part of the world where there still remain vestiges of free enterprise, despite Hartmann's criticism of them. Isn't the life expectancy drastically greater now than at any point in human history? This is of course not all due to government; rather, it is in spite of this institution's interferences with the market place that we have progressed in this way. Why, then, not allow us as humans to freely interact with one another without undue government interference with our liberties? Let us at least try, and see what cooperating human beings can accomplish. The obvious result would be vastly superior roads, schools, security, currency "stability" and most importantly to us as libertarians, protection of basic human freedom and liberty.

7. Conclusion

Both of Hartmann's two claims can easily be refuted. The first rests simply on the assertion, without argument, that only government can provide the necessary infrastructure for trade and economic activity. In fact, not only is this false, but it is difficult to imagine any worse system for providing these amenities. Furthermore, in contrast to Hartmann's second claim, government provision of these goods and services ensures that they are provided in a political fashion, hence that they benefit the moneyed classes at the expense of the poor and his much beloved middle class. The state tends to prop up established businesses, preventing the poor and middle classes from moving ahead in the world by competing with older firms. When our politicians prop up the inefficient, they impoverish virtually the entire nation, even including, paradoxically, some of the recipients of this largess, who, after all, are also consumers. The second rests on the idea, fundamentally at odds with the most basic economic truths, that tariffs benefit anyone. To believe that preventing two parties from trading can benefit either of them is so at odds with economics and common sense as to invite ridicule, not agreement.

Notwithstanding the way Hartmann frames the argument, of course, seeing the utter lack of sense of his claims need not imply support for something called "conservative economics." Indeed, those he identifies as advocating this conservative economics--Reagan, Hoover, Hamilton, and Adams, are themselves interventionists of the first order. They were supporters of central banking, (26) one of the most destructive interventions practiced by governments. Ironically, they favored many of the interferences that Hartmann himself invokes in his argument for his first point--regulations that benefit the rich and the business-owner at the expense of the poor and middle classes. Rejection of Hartmann's ideas ought to lead us, far from conservative policies, to libertarian policies--to the rejection of government intervention, regardless of whom they claim to benefit.

REFERENCES

Adie, Douglas K. (1988), Monopoly Mail: Privatizing the United States Postal Service. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

Adie, Douglas K. (1990a), The Mail Monopoly: Analyzing Canadian Postal Service. Vancouver: The Fraser Institute.

Adie, Douglas K. (1990b), "Why Marginal Reform of the U.S. Postal Service Won't Succeed," in Peter J. Ferrara, (ed.), Free the Mail: Ending the Postal Monopoly. Washington, DC: The Cato Institute.

Ahlbrandt, Roger (1973), "Efficiency in the Provision of Fire Services," Public Choice 16(Fall): 1-15.

Alston, Wilton D. (2007), "What Would Happen if the Post Office Had Competition?" June 6; http://www.lewrockwell.com/alston/alston21.html

Anderson, Terry L., and Peter J. Hill (1979), "An American Experiment in Anarcho-Capitalism: The Not So Wild, Wild West," Journal of Libertarian Studies 3: 9-29; http://mises.org/journals/jls/3_1/3_1_2.pdf

Anderson, Terry L., and Peter J. Hill, (ed.) (1996), The Privatization Process: A Worldwide Perspective. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

Anderson, William L. (2000), "The Legacy of Progressivism," January 10; http://mises.org/daily/364

Anderson, William L. (2002), "The U.S. Economy Is Not Depression-Proof," July 24; http://mises.org/daily/1008

Askari, Hossein, and Noureddine Krichene (2011), "Paul versus Bernanke," January 5; http://www.lewrockwell.com/orig 12/askari1.1.1.html

Bagus, Philipp (2011), "Will There Be QE3, QE4, QE5 ...?" January 4; http://www.lewrockwell.com/orig10/bagus2.1.1.html

Baird, Charles (1990), "American Union Law: Sources of Conflict," Journal of Labor Research 11(3): 269-292.

Baird, Charles (2000), "Unions and Antitrust," Journal of Labor Research 21(4): 585-600.

Bastiat, Frederic (1962), The Law. New York: Foundation for Economic Education.

Beck, Glenn (2003), The Real America: Messages from the Heart and Heartland. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Beck, Glenn (2007), An Inconvenient Book: Real Solutions to the World's Biggest Problems. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Beck, Glenn (2009A), Glenn Beck's Common Sense: The Case against an Outof-Control Government. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Beck, Glenn (2009B), Arguing with Idiots: How to Stop Small Minds and Big Government. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Beck, Glenn (2010), Broke: The Plan to Restore Our Trust, Truth, and Treasure. New York: Simon & Schuster.

Bennett, James T. (1980), Better Government at Half the Price. London: Green Hill Publishers.

Bennett, James T., and Manuel H. Johnson (1980), "Tax Reduction without Sacrifice: Private Sector Production of Public Services," Public Finance Quarterly 8(4): 363-396.

Blair, Roger D., Paul B. Ginsberg, and Ronald J. Vogel (1975), "Blue Cross-Blue Shield Administration Costs: A Study of Non-Profit Health Insurers," Economic Inquiry 13(2): 237-251.

Bennett, James T., and Thomas DiLorenzo (1982), "Public Employee Unions and the Privatization of Public Services," Journal of Labor Research 4(1): 33-45.

Bennett, James T., and Thomas DiLorenzo (1989), Unfair Competition: The Profits of NonProfits. New York: Hamilton Press.

Benson, Bruce L. (1988), "Legal Evolution in Primitive Societies," Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 144: 772-788.

Benson, Bruce L. (1989A), "Enforcement of Private Property Rights in Primitive Societies: Law without Government," The Journal of Libertarian Studies, 9(1): 126; http://mises.org/journals/jls/9_1/9_1_1.pdf

Benson, Bruce L. (1989B), "The Spontaneous Evolution of Commercial Law," Southern Economic Journal 55: 644-661.

Benson, Bruce L. (1990A), "Customary Law with Private Means of Resolving Disputes and Dispensing Justice: A Description of a Modern System of Law and Order without State Coercion," Journal of Libertarian Studies, 9(2): 25-42; http://mises.org/journals/jls/9_2/9_2_2.pdf

Benson, Bruce L. (1990B), The Enterprise of Law: Justice without the State. San Francisco: Pacific Research Institute for Public Policy

Benson, Bruce L. (1991), "Reciprocal Exchange as the Basis for Recognition of Law: Examples from American History," Journal of Libertarian Studies 10(3): 53-82.

Benson, Bruce L. (1994), "Are Public Goods Really Common Pools? Considerations of the Evolution of Policing and Highways in England," Economic Inquiry 32(2): 294-71.

Benson, Bruce L. (1998), To Serve and Protect: Privatization and Community in Criminal Justice. New York, NY: New York University Press.

Bergland, David (1986), Libertarianism in One Lesson, 2nd ed. Orpheus Publications: Berkeley Hills Books.

Bibeault, Zach (2009), "Want to Shrink the Economy? Limit the Labor Force," September 18; http://mises.org/daily/3690

Block, Walter, Joseph Horton and Debbie Walker (1998), "The Necessity of Free Trade," Journal of Markets and Morality 1(2): 192-200.

Block, Walter, and Chris Arakaky (2008), "Taking Government Money for Grad School?" May 23; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block100.html

Block, Walter, and Tom DiLorenzo (2000), "Is Voluntary Government Possible? A Critique of Constitutional Economics," Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 156(4): 567-582; http://www.walterblock.com/publications/voluntary_govt.pdf

Block, Walter, and Tom DiLorenzo (2001), "The Calculus of Consent Revisited," Public Finance and Management 1(3); http://www.spaef.com/PFM_PUB/pubv1n3.html

Block, Walter, and William Barnett II (2008), "Continuums," Journal Etica e Politica/Ethics & Politics 1(2): 151-166; http://www2. units.it/~etica/2008_1/BLOCKBARNETT.pdf

Block, Walter E., and Michael Fleischer (2010), "How Would an Anarchist Society Handle Child Abuse?" October 13; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/ block167.html

Block, Walter (1972), "The Polish Ham Question," The Libertarian Forum 4(67): 5; http://www.mises.org/journals/lf/1972/1972_06-07.pdf; http://mises.org/daily/4054; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block143.html

Block, Walter (1984), "Book review" of John Anderson and Morley Gunderson, Union-Management Relations in Canada. Don Mills, Ontario: Addison-Wesley Publishers, 1982; in Journal of Labor Research 5(1): 103-105.

Block, Walter (1991), "Labor Relations, Unions and Collective Bargaining: A Political Economic Analysis," Journal of Social Political and Economic Studies 16(4): 477-507.

Block, Walter (1996A), "Labor Market Disputes: A Comment on Albert Rees' 'Fairness in Wage Distribution,'" Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics 7(3): 217230.

Block, Walter (1996B), "Comment on Richard B. Freeman's 'Labor Markets and Institutions in Economic Development,'" International Journal of Social Economics 23(1): 6-16.

Block, Walter (2002A), "Accepting Government Subsidies," Fraser Forum, February, 27; http://oldfraser.lexi.net/publications/forum/2002/02/section_13.html

Block, Walter (2002B), "Henry Simons Is Not a Supporter of Free Enterprise," Journal of Libertarian Studies 16(4): 3-36; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/16_4/16_4_2.pdf.

Block, Walter (2003), "National Defense and the Theory of Externalities, Public Goods and Clubs," in Hans-Hermann Hoppe (ed.), The Myth of National Defense: Essays on the Theory and History of Security Production. Auburn: Mises Institute, pp. 301-334; http://www.mises.org/etexts/defensemyth.pdf

Block, Walter (2004), "Radical Libertarianism: Applying Libertarian Principles to Dealing with the Unjust Government, Part I," Reason Papers 27(3): 117-133; http://www.walterblock.com/publications/block_radical-libertarianism- rp.pdf

Block, Walter (2005), "Governmental Inevitability: Reply to Holcombe," Journal of Libertarian Studies 19(3): 71-93; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/19_ 3/19_3_4.pdf

Block, Walter (2006), "Radical Libertarianism: Applying Libertarian Principles to Dealing with the Unjust Government, Part II," Reason Papers 28(1): 85-109; http: //www.walterblock.com/publications/block_radical-libertarianism-rp.pdf

Block, Walter (2007A), "Anarchism and Minarchism; No Rapprochement Possible: Reply to Tibor Machan," Journal of Libertarian Studies 21(1): 91-99; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/21_1/21_1_5.pdf

Block, Walter (2007B), "Ron Paul and Matching Funds," October 1; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block86.html

Block, Walter (2008), "Replies to Readers," September 23; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block108.html (libertarians hypocrites for using public school?)

Block, Walter (2009A), "Libertarian Punishment Theory: Working for, and Donating to, the State" Libertarian Papers 1; http://libertarianpapers.org/2009/17- libertarianpunishment-theory-working-for-and-donating-to-the-state/

Block, Walter (2009B), "Toward a Libertarian Theory of Guilt and Punishment for the Crime of Statism," in Hulsmann, Jorg Guido, and Stephan Kinsella (eds.), Property, Freedom and Society: Essays in Honor of Hans-Hermann Hoppe. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 137-148; http://mises.org/books/hulsmann-kinsella_property- freedom-society-2009.pdf

Block, Walter (2010A), "You Are a Rotten Kid (Rent Control and Libertarianism)," February 27; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block150.html

Block, Walter (2010B), "Are Unions Criminal Gangs?" Global Virtue Ethics Review 6(1): 28-49; http://www.spaef.com/article.php?id=1176; http://www.spaef.com/file.php?id=1176

Block, Walter (Forthcoming A), "Toward a Libertarian Theory of Guilt and Punishment for the Crime of Statism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 25.

Block, Walter (Forthcoming B), "Hoppe, Kinsella and Rothbard II on Immigration: A Critique," Journal of Libertarian Studies 25.

Block, Walter (2010), "Rejoinder to Machan on Anarchism and Limited Statism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 24.

Boardman, Anthony, and Aidan R. Vining (1989), "Ownership and Performance in Competitive Environments: A Comparison of the Performance of Private, Mixed, and State-Owned Enterprises," Journal of Law and Economics 32: 1-33.

Borcherding, T.E., Burnaby, B.C., Pommerehne, W.W., and F. Schneider (1982), "Comparing the Efficiency of Private and Public Production: The Evidence from Five Countries," Zeitschriftfur Nationalokonomie 89: 127-56.

Borcherding, Thomas (ed.) (1977), Budgets and Bureaucrats: The Sources of Government Growth. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Brandly, Mark (2002), "A Primer on Trade," November 4; http://www.mises.org/article.aspx?Id=1084

Bresciani-Turrino, Constantino (2007), Economics of Inflation: A Study of Currency Depreciation in Post-War Germany. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

Brown, Pamela J. (1987), "Free Thought and Free Trade: The Analogy between Scientific and Entrepreneurial Discovery Process," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 8(2): 289-292; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/8_2/8_2_8.pdf

Butler, Stuart M. (1985), Privatizing Federal Spending. New York: Universe Books.

Butler, Stuart M. (1986), "Privatizing Bulk Mail," Management 6(1).

Caplan, Bryan, and Stringham, Edward (2003), "Networks, Law, and the Paradox of Cooperation," Review of Austrian Economics 16(4): 309-326.

Caplan, Bryan, and Stringham, Edward (2008), "Privatizing the Adjudication of Disputes," Theoretical Inquiries in Law 9(2).

Chapman, John L. (2008), "The Privatization of Public Services," February 21; http://mises.org/story/2866

Chappell, Robert H. (1978), "Anarchy Revisited: An Inquiry into the Public Education Dilemma," Journal of Libertarian Studies 2(4): 357-372; https://mises.org/journals/jls/2_4/2_4_7.pdf

Clarkson, Kenneth W. (1972), "Some Implications of Property Rights in Hospital Management," Journal of Law and Economics 15(2): 363-384.

Crain, W. Mark, and Asghar Zardkoohi (1978), "A Test of the Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Water Utilities in the United States," Journal of Law and Economics 21(2): 395-408.

Davies, David G. (1971), "The Efficiency of Public Versus Private Firms: The Case of Australia's Two Airlines," Journal of Law and Economics 14(1): 149-165.

Davies, David G. (1977), "Property Rights and Economic Efficiency--The Australian Airlines Revisited," Journal of Law & Economics 20(1): 223-226.

Coulson, Andrew J. (2008), "The Real Cost of Public Schools"; http://www.cato-at-liberty.org/2008/04/07/the-real-cost-of-public-schools/

Cowen, Tyler (1992), "Law as a Public Good: The Economics of Anarchy," Economics and Philosophy 8: 249.

Cowen, Tyler (1994), "Rejoinder to David Friedman on the Economics of Anarchy," Economics and Philosophy 10: 329.

Cox, Wendell (1998), "U.S. Public Schools and Private Schools: Performance and Spending Compared," The Public Purpose 18; January; http://www.publicpurpose.com/pp-edpp.htm

Cuzan, Alfred G. (1979), "Do We Ever Really Get Out of Anarchy?" The Journal of Libertarian Studies 3(2): 151-158.

D'Amico, Dan, and Walter Block (2007), "A Legal and Economic Analysis of Graffiti," Humanomics 23(1): 29-38; http://www.mises.org/journals/scholar/damico.pdf;

De Alessi, Louis (1982), "On the Nature and Consequence of Private and Public Enterprises," Minnesota Law Review 67(1): 179-286.

de Molinari, Gustave (1977), The Production of Security. New York: Center for Libertarian Studies.

Dewenter, Kathrin, and Paul H. Malatesta (2000), "State-Owned and Privately-Owned Firms: An Empirical Analysis of Profitability, Leverage, and Labor Intensity," American Economic Review 91(1): 320-334.

DiLorenzo, Thomas J. (2010), "The Culture of Violence in the American West: Myth versus Reality." The Independent Review 15(2): 227-239; http://www.mdependent.org/pdf/tir/tir_15_02_4_dilorenzo.pdf

DiLorenzo, Tom, and Walter Block (2001), "Constitutional Economics and the Calculus of Consent," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 15(3): 37-56; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/15_3/15_3_2.pdf

Domhoff, G. William (1967), Who Rules America? Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

Domhoff, G. William (1998), Who Rules America? Power and Politics in the Year 2000, 3rd ed. Santa Cruz: University of California

D'Souza, Juliet D., Bernardo Bortolotti, Marcella Fantini, and William L. Megginson (2000), "Sources of Performance Improvements in Privatized Firms: A Clinical Study of the Global Telecommunications Industry," Working Paper, Price College of Business, University of Oklahoma

Evans, Jason, and Walter Block (2002), "Labor Union Policies: Gains or Pains?" Cross Cultural Management 9(1): 71-79.

Fielding, Karl T. (1978), "The Role of Personal Justice in Anarcho-capitalism," Journal of Libertarian Studies 2(3): 239-242.

Fitzgerald, Randall (1989). When Government Goes Private: Successful Alternatives to Public Services. New York: Universe Books.

Frech III, H.E. (1976), "The Property Rights Theory of the Firm: Empirical Results from a Natural Experiment," Journal of Political Economy 84(1): 143-152.

Friedman, David (1989), The Machinery of Freedom: Guide to a Radical Capitalism, 2nd ed. La Salle, IL: Open Court; http://www.daviddfriedman.com/Libertarian/ Machinery_of_Freedom/MofF_Chapter_41.html

Friedman, David D. (1994), "Law as a Private Good: A Response to Tyler Cowen on the Economics of Anarchy," Economics and Philosophy 10: 319.

Friedman, Milton, and Rose Friedman (1997), "The Case for Free Trade," Hoover Digest 4; http://www.hooverdigest.org/974/friedman.html

Garrison, Roger W. (2001), Time and Money: The Macroeconomics of Capital Structure. London: Routledge. (an important contribution to Austrian business cycle theory)

Gatto, John Taylor (2000), The Underground History of American Education. Oxford Village Press, Odysseus Group.

Gatto, John Taylor (2002A), Dumbing Us Down: The Hidden Curriculum of Compulsory Schooling, 2nd ed. New Society Publishers.

Gatto, John Taylor (2002B), The Exhausted School: Bending the Bars of Traditional Education, 2nd ed. Berkeley Hills Books.

Goodman, Paul, Ivan Illich, John Holt, Dayna Martin, and John Taylor Gatto (2010), Deschooling and Criticism of the School System: Unschooling. Books LLC.

Gwartney, James, Robert Lawson, and Walter Block (1996), Economic Freedom of the World, 1975-1995. Vancouver, B.C.: the Fraser Institute.

Hanke, Steve H. (1987a), "Privatization," in J. Eatwell, M. Milgate and P. Newman (eds.), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, Vol. 3. London: Macmillan, 976-77.

Hanke, Steve H. (ed.) (1987b), Prospects for Privatization. New York: Academy of Political Science.

Hanke, Steve H. (ed.) (1987c), Privatization and Development. San Francisco: Institute for Contemporary Studies.

Hartmann, Thom (2004), "Democracy--Not 'The Free Market'--Will Save America's Middle Class." March 12; http://www.commondreams.org/views04/031208.htm

Hasnas, John (1995), "The Myth of the Rule of Law." Wisconsin Law Review 199; http://faculty.msb.edu/hasnasj/GTWebSite/MythWeb.htm

Hayek, Friedrich A. (1988), The Fatal Conceit: The Errors of Socialism, Bartley, W. W., III (ed.). London: Routledge.

Hayek, Friedrich A. (1931), Prices and Production, London: Routledge. Hazlitt, Henry (2008 [1946]). Economics in One Lesson. Auburn, AL: Mises Institute.

Heinrich, David J. (2010). "Justice for All without the State," The Libertarian Standard, May 6; http://www.libertarianstandard.com/articles/david-j-heinrich/justicefor-all- without-the-state/

Heldman, Daniel C. (1977), American Labor Unions: Political Values and Financial Structure. Washington, DC: Council on American Affairs.

Heldman, Daniel C., James T. Bennett, and Manuel Johnson (1981), Deregulating Labor Relations. Dallas: Fisher Institute.

Herbener, Jeffrey M. (2002), "After the Age of Inflation: Austrian Proposals for Monetary Reform," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 5(4): 5-19.

Herbert, Auberon (1978 [1885]), The Right and Wrong of Compulsion by the State and Other Essays, Eric Mack (ed.). Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

Higgs, Robert (2009), "Why We Couldn't Abolish Slavery Then and Can't Abolish Government Now," August 20; http://www.lewrockwell.com/higgs/higgs128.html

Holcombe, Randall G. (2004), "Government: Unnecessary but Inevitable," The Independent Review 3(3): 325-342.

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (1990), "Marxist and Austrian Class Analysis," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 9(2): 79-94; http://mises.org/journals/jls/9_2/9_2_5.pdf

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (1993), The Economics and Ethics of Private Property: Studies in Political Economy and Philosophy. Boston: Kluwer.

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2001A), Democracy--The God That Failed: The Economics and Politics of Monarchy, Democracy, and Natural Order. Rutgers University, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2001B), "Anarcho-Capitalism: An Annotated Bibliography," December 31; http://lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe5.html

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (ed.) (2003), "National Defense and the Theory of Externalities, Public Goods and Clubs," Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (ed.), The Myth of National Defense: Essays on the Theory and History of Security Production. Auburn: Mises Institute.

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2008a), "Reflections on the Origin and the Stability of the State," June 23; http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe18.html

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann (2008b), "On the Impossibility of Limited Government and the Prospects for a Second American Revolution," June 30; http://www.lewrockwell.com/hoppe/hoppe19.html

Huebert, Jacob (2010), Libertarianism Today. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger.

Hughes, Jonathan R.T. (1977), The Governmental Habit: Economic Controls from Colonial Times to the Present. New York: Basic Books.

Hulsmann, J.G. (2008), The Ethics of Money Production. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

Hummel, Jeffrey Rogers (2001), "The Will to Be Free: The Role of Ideology in National Defense," Independent Review 4(1): 523-537.

Hutt, W.H. (1973), The Strike Threat System: The Economic Consequences of Collective Bargaining, New Rochelle, NY: Arlington House.

Hutt, W. H. (1989), "Trade Unions: The Private Use of Coercive Power," The Review of Austrian Economics 3: 109-120; http://www.mises.org/journals/rae/pdf/rae3_1_7.pdf.

Johnsson, Richard C.B. (2004), "On Ricardo and Free Trade," January 12; http://www.mises.org/article.aspx?Id=1421&

King, Seth (2010), "Daily Anarchist Interviews: Walter Block," September 9; http://www.lewrockwell.com/block/block165.html

Kinsella, Stephan N. (1995), "Legislation and the Discovery of Law in a Free Society," Journal of Libertarian Studies 11(2): 132.

Kinsella, Stephan N. (1996), "New Rationalist Directions in Libertarian Rights Theory," Journal of Libertarian Studies 12(2): 313-326; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/12_2/12_2_5.pdf

Kinsella, Stephan N. (2004), "What It Means to Be an Anarcho-Capitalist," January 20; http://www.lewrockwell.com/kinsella/kinsella15.html

Kinsella, Stephan N. (2009), "The Irrelevance of the Impossibility of AnarchoLibertarianism," August 20; http://www.stephankinsella.com/2009/08/20/the-irrelevance-of-the- impossibility-of-anarcho-libertarianism/

Kolko, Gabriel (1963), Triumph of Conservatism. Chicago: Quadrangle Books.

Landsburg, Steven E. (2008), "What to Expect When You're Free Trading," The New York Times, January 16; http://www.nytimes.com/2008/01/16/opinion/ 16landsburg.html?_r=1&scp=1&sq=Steven+E.+Landsburg&oref=slogin.

Leeson, Peter T. (2007a), "Efficient Anarchy," Public Choice 130(1-2): 41-53.

Leeson, Peter T. (2007b), "Review of Edward P. Stringham, (ed.), Anarchy and the Law," Public Choice 133: 253-256.

Leeson, Peter T. (2007c), "Trading with Bandits," Journal of Law and Economics 50(2): 303-321.

Leeson, Peter T. (2007d), "Anarchy Unbound, or: Why Self-Governance Works Better than You Think," August 6; http://www.cato-unbound.org/2007/08/06/petert- leeson/anarchy-unbound-or-why-self-governance-works-better-than-youthink/

Leeson, Peter T., and Edward P. Stringham (2005), "Is Government Inevitable? Comment on Holcombe's Analysis," Independent Review 9(4): 543-549.

Liggio, Leonard P., and Peden, Joseph R. (1978), "Social Scientists, Schooling and the Acculturation of Immigrants in 19th Century America," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 2(1): 69-84; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/2_1/2_1_6.pdf

Limbaugh, Rush (1992), The Way Things Ought to Be. Pocket Books.

Limbaugh, Rush (1993), See, I Told You So. Pocket Books.

Lindsay, Cotton M. (1976), "A Theory of Government Enterprise," Journal of Political Economy 84: 1061-1077.

Long, Roderick (1998), "Why Objective Law Requires Anarchy," http://libertariannation.org/a/f61l1.html

Long, Roderick (2003), "Anarchism as Constitutionalism: A Reply to Bidinotto," December 7; http://praxeology.net/unblog12-03.htm#02;

Long, Roderick (2004), "Libertarian Anarchism: Responses to Ten Objections," http://www.lewrockwell.com/long/long 11.html

Long, Roderick (Undated), "About Market Anarchism: A Bibliography," Molinari Institute; http://praxeology.net/anarcres.htm

Megginson, William L., and Jeffry M. Netter (2000), "From State to Market: A Survey of Empirical Studies on Privatization," New York Stock Exchange Working Paper 98-05.

Megginson, William L., and Jeffry M. Netter (2001), "From State to Market: A Survey of Empirical Studies on Privatization," Journal of Economic Literature 39(2): 321-389.

Mises, Ludwig von ([1912] 1953), The Theory of Money and Credit [originally published in German in 1912]. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Mises, Ludwig von ([1949] 1998), Human Action, Scholars' Edition. Auburn: Mises Institute.

Mises, Ludwig von (1978), The Clash of Group Interests and Other Essays. New York: Center for Libertarian Studies. http://www.mises.org/etexts/mises/clash/clash.asp

Molyneux, Stefan (2007), "Stateless Dictatorships: How a Free Society Prevents the Re-emergence of a Government," June 27; http://www.lewrockwell.com/molyneux/molyneux37.html

Molyneux, Stefan (2008), "The Stateless Society: An Examination of Alternatives," http://www.mail- archive.com/libertarianenterprise@yahoogroups.com/msg02056.html

Monsen, J. R., and K.D. Walters (1983), Nationalized Companies. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Moore, Stephen, and Stuart Butler (eds.) (1987), Privatization. Washington: Heritage Foundation.

Moore, Stephen (1987), "Privatizing the U.S. Postal Service," in Stephen Moore and Stuart Butler (eds.), Privatization. Washington: Heritage Foundation.

Moore, Thomas G. (1990), "The Federal Postal Monopoly: History, Rationale, and Future," in Peter J. Ferrara (ed.), Free the Mail: Ending the Postal Monopoly. Washington, DC: CATO Institute

Murphy, Robert P. (2002), Chaos Theory: Two Essays on Market Anarchy. New York: RJ Communications LLC.

Murphy, Robert P. (2004), "Can Trade Bring Poverty?" December 24; http://www.mises.org/article.aspx?Id=1699

Murphy, Robert P. (2005), "But Wouldn't Warlords Take Over?" July 7; http://mises.org/story/1855

Murphy, Robert P. (2009A), Politically Incorrect Guide to the Great Depression and the New Deal. Regnery.

Murphy, Robert P. (2009B), "Christina Romer's Faulty Depression History," July 6;

Murphy, Robert P. (2010A), "Krugman's Hoover History," March 22; http://mises.org/daily/4197

Murphy, Robert P. (2010B), "Did Hoover Really Slash Spending?" May 31; http://mises.org/daily/4350

Murphy, Robert P. (2011), "Interwar Presidents and the Fantasies of Historians," January 3; http://mises.org/daily/4882

Narveson, Jan (1988), The Libertarian Idea. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

National Assessment of Educational Progress (2006), Comparing Private Schools and Public Schools Using Hierarchical Linear Modeling, http://nces.ed.gov/nationsreportcard/pdf/studies/2006461 .pdf

Nock, Albert Jay (1935), Our Enemy the State; http://www.barefootsworld.net/nockoets0.html

Nozick, Robert (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.

Oppenheimer, Franz (1914, 1975), The State. New York: Free Life Editions.

Osterfeld, David (1989), "Anarchism and the Public Goods Issue: Law, Courts and the Police," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 9(1): 47-68; http://www.mises.org/journals/j ls/9_1/9_1_3.pdf

Paul, Ron (2010), End the Fed. New York, NY: Grand Central Publishing.

Perkins, Richard, and Ernestine Perkens (1971), Precondition for Peace and Prosperity: Rational Anarchy. Ontario: Phibbs Printing World.

Petro, Sylvester (1957), The Labor Policy of the Free Society. New York: Ronald Press.

Poole, Robert (1976), Cutting Back City Hall. New York: Reason Press.

Postiglione, Gerard (1982), "The Opponents of Public Education: New York State, 1870-1880," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 6(3-4): 359-376; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/6_3/6_3_11 .pdf

Powell, Benjamin and Christopher Coyne (2003), "Do Pessimistic Assumptions about Human Behavior Justify Government?" The Journal of Libertarian Studies 17(4): 17-38.

Powell, Benjamin, and Bart Wilson (2008), "An Experimental Investigation of Hobbesian Jungles," Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 66(3-4): 669-686.

Powell, Benjamin, Ryan Ford, and Alex Nowrasteh (Forthcoming), "Somalia after State Collapse: Chaos or Improvement," Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 69.

Priest, George (1975), "The History of the Postal Monopoly in the United States," Journal of Law and Economics 18(1): 33-80.

Raico, Ralph (1977), "Classical Liberal Exploitation Theory: A Comment on Professor Liggio's Paper," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 1(3): 179-184.

Reynolds, Morgan O. (1984), Power and Privilege: Labor Unions in America. New York: Manhattan Institute for Policy Research.

Reynolds, Morgan O. (1987), Making America Poorer: The Cost of Labor Law. Washington DC: Cato Institute.

Reynolds, Morgan O. (2009), "A History of Labor Unions from Colonial Times to 2009," July 17: http://mises.org/daily/3553

Ricardo, David (1821 [1912]), The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, 3rd ed. London: J.M. Dent.

Rockwell, Jr. Llewellyn H. (2001), "Liberty and the Common Good," December 31; http://www.mises.org/article.aspx?Id=860

Rockwell Jr., Llewellyn H. (2008), "Don't Trust the Brain Trust," October 7; http://mises.org/daily/3145

Rothbard, Murray N. ([1963] 1975), America's Great Depression. Kansas City: Sheed and Ward; http://www.mises.org/rothbard/agd.pdf

Rothbard, Murray N. (1966A), "Herbert Clark Hoover: A Reconsideration," New Individualist Review Winter: 3-12.

Rothbard, Murray N. (1966B), "The Hoover Myth," review of The Poverty of Abundance: Hoover, the Nation, the Depression, by A.U. Romasco. Studies on the Left, July-August, 70-84. Reprinted in J. Weinstein and D. Eakin (eds.), For a New America: Essays in History and Politics. New York: Random House, 1970, 162-179.

Rothbard, Murray N. (1972), "Herbert Hoover and the Myth of Laissez Faire," Ronald Radosh, and Murray Rothbard (eds.), A New History of Leviathan. New York: E.P. Dutton, http://mises.org/books/newhistoryleviathan.pdf

Rothbard, Murray N. (1973), For a New Liberty. New York: Macmillan; http://www.mises.org/rothbard/newliberty.asp

Rothbard, Murray N. (1978), "Society without a State," J.R. Pennock and J.W. Chapman (eds.), Anarchism: Nomos XIX. New York: New York University Press, 191-207.

Rothbard, Murray N. (1983), The Mystery of Banking. New York: Richardson and Snyder.

Rothbard, Murray N. (1990), What Has Government Done to Our Money? Auburn, AL: Mises Institute; http://www.mises.org/rothbard/rothmoney.pdf

Rothbard, Murray N. (1993 [2004]), Man, Economy and State. Auburn AL: Mises Institute; http://www.mises.org/rothbard/mes.asp

Rothbard, Murray N. (1998 [1982]), The Ethics of Liberty. New York: New York University Press; http://www.mises.org/rothbard/ethics/ethics.asp

Rothbard, Murray N. (2006), "Education: Free and Compulsory," http://mises.org/daily/2226

Rothbard, Murray N. (2008), "Are Libertarians 'Anarchists'?"; http://www.lewrockwell.com/rothbard/rothbard167.html

Rummell, R.J. (2007), "Yes, Our Most Extensive Society Is an Anarchy," August 5; http://freedomspeace.blogspot.com/2007/08/yes-our-most-extensive- society-is.html

Savas, E.S. (1979), "Refuse Collection: A Critical Review of the Evidence," Journal of Urban Analysis 6: 1-13.

Savas, E.S. 1982. How to Shrink Government: Privatizing the Public Sector. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers.

Savas, E.S. (1987), Privatization. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers.

Savas, E.S. (2000), Privatization and Public--Private Partnerships. Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers.

Schmidt, Emerson P. (1973), Union Power and the Public Interest. Los Angeles: Nash.

Schumpeter, Joseph A. (1942), Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. New York: Harper.

Sechrest, Larry J. (1999), "Rand, Anarchy, and Taxes," The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 1(1): 87-105.

Shea, Brian (2010), "Solidarity Forever: The Power Invested in Worker Collectives under United States Law," Journal of Libertarian Studies 22: 219-246; http://mises.org/journals/jls/22_1/22_1_11.pdf

Smith, Adam ([1776], 1979), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

Smith, George (1979), "Justice Entrepreneurship in a Free Market," Journal of Libertarian Studies 3: 405; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/3_4/3_4_4.pdf

Sneed, John D. (1977), "Order without Law: Where Will Anarchists Keep the Madmen?" The Journal of Libertarian Studies 1(2): 117-124.

Spencer, Herbert (1970), Social Statics. New York: Robert Schalkenbach Foundation.

Spencer, Herbert (1981), The Man Versus the State. Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.

Spooner, Lysander (1966 [1870]), No Treason: The Constitution of No Authority and a Letter to Thomas F. Bayard. Larkspur, CO: Rampart College; http://www.lysanderspooner.org/notreason.htm

Stolyarov II, Gennady (2009), "Murphy on the Great Confusion," November 25; https://mises.org/daily/3858

Strasnick, Steven (1979), "Justice Entrepreneurship in a Free Market: A Comment," Journal of Libertarian Studies 3(4): 433-437; http://mises.org/journals/jls/3_4/3_4_6.pdf

Stringham, Edward (1998-1999), "Justice without Government," Journal of Libertarian Studies 14(1): 53-77.

Stringham, Edward (1999), "Market Chosen Law," Journal of Libertarian Studies 14(1): 53-77.

Stringham, Edward (2002), "The Emergence of the London Stock Exchange as a Self-Policing Club," Journal of Private Enterprise 17(2): 1-19.

Stringham, Edward (2003), "The Extralegal Development of Securities Trading in Seventeenth Century Amsterdam," Quarterly Review of Economics and Finance 43(2): 321-344.

Stringham, Edward (ed.) (2005a), Anarchy, State, and Public Choice. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

Stringham, Edward (2005b), "The Capability of Government in Providing Protection Against Online Fraud: Are Classical Liberals Guilty of the Nirvana Fallacy?" Journal of Law, Economics, and Policy 1(2): 371-392.

Stringham, Edward (2006), "Overlapping Jurisdictions, Proprietary Communities, and Competition in the Realm of Law," Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 162(3): 516-534.

Stringham, Edward, ed. (2007), Anarchy and the Law: The Political Economy of Choice. Somerset, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

Tannehill, Morris, and Linda Tannehill ([1970] 1984), The Market for Liberty. New York: Laissez Faire Books; http://www.lewrockwell.com/orig11/tannehill1.html

Thies, Clifford F. (2010), "The Making Up of a President," August 5; http://mises.org/daily/4589

Thornton, Mark (2010), "Hoover, Bush, and Great Depressions," Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 13(3): 86-100; http://mises.org/journals/qjae/pdf /qjae13_3_6.pdf

Tinsley, Patrick (1998-1999), "With Liberty and Justice for All: A Case for Private Police," Journal of Libertarian Studies 14(1): 95-100; http://www.mises.org/journals/jls/14_1/14_1_5.pdf

Vining, Aidan R., and Anthony E. Boardman (1992), "Ownership versus Competition: Efficiency in Public Enterprise," Public Choice 73: 205-39.

Westley, Christopher (2005), "The New Deal in One Lesson," May 26; https://mises.org/daily/1816

White, Lawrence H. (1978), "Privatization of Municipally-provided Services," The Journal of Libertarian Studies 2(2): 187-197.

Wollstein, Jarret B. (1969), "Society without Coercion," in Society without Government. New York: Arno Press

Woods, Thomas E. Jr. (2009), Meltdown: A Free-Market Look at Why the Stock Market Collapsed, the Economy Tanked, and Government Bailouts Will Make Things Worse. Washington DC: Regnery Publishing.

Woolridge, William C. (1970). Uncle Sam the Monopoly Man. New Rochelle, NY: Arlington House.

Young, Andrew, and Walter Block (1999), "Enterprising Education: Doing Away with the Public School System," International Journal of Value Based Management 12(3): 195-207; http://www.mises.org/etexts/enterprisingedu.pdf; http://www.mises.org/story/2216; http://www.walterblock.com/publications/enterprising_education.pdf

REFERENCES

(1.) For example, Walter Cronkite, Tom Brokaw, Dan Rather, Peter Jennings.

(2.) See in this regard Beck, 2003, 2007, 2009A, 2009B, 2010; Limbaugh, 1992, 1993.

(3.) For another critique of Hartmann, see also Bibeault, 2009.

(4.) http://www.thomhartmann.com/

(5.) http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/3036677/

(6.) Askari and Krichene. 2011; http://financeprices.info/the-usa-dollar-has-lost96-since-the-federal- reserve-began-in1913/;http://www.24hgold.com/english/news-gold-silver- us-dollar-has-lost-96-of-value-since-federal-reserve-creation- in 1913.aspx?contributor=Charleston+Voice&article=908683662G10020& redirect=False; http://kommoncents.blogspot.com/2010/10/dollar-has-lost-95-of-its- value-since.html

(7.) For a critique of Hartmann's view that we can inflate our way out of depression, and into prosperity, see Bagus, 2011; Bresciani-Turrino, 2007; Herbener, 2002; Huelsmann, 2008; Mises, 1953; Rothbard, 1990

(8.) For the advantages of private over public sector courts, police and law, both in terms of morality and practicality, see Anderson and Hill, 1979; Benson, 1988, 1989A, 1989B, 1990A, 1990B, 1991, 1994, 1998; Block, 2003, 2004, 2005, 2006, 2007A; Block and DiLorenzo, 2000, 2001; Caplan and Stringham, 2003, forthcoming 2008; Cowen, 1992, 1994; Cuzan, 1979; DiLorenzo and Block, 2001; Fielding, 1978; Friedman, 1989, 1994; Hasnas, 1995; Herbert, 1978; Holcombe, 2004; Hoppe, 1993, 2001a, 2001b, 2003, 2008a, 2008b; Hummel, 2001; Kinsella, 2004; Leeson, 2007a, 2007b, 2007c, 2007c, 2007d; Leeson and Stringham, 2005; Long, undated, 1998, 2003, 2004; Molinari, 1977; Molyneux, 2007; Murphy, 2002, 2005; Nock, 1935; Oppenheimer, 1975; Osterfeld, 1989; R. and E. Perkens, 1971; Powell and Coyne, 2003; Powell and Wilson, 2008; Powell, Ford, and Nowrasteh, Forthcoming; Rothbard, 1973, 1978, 1982, 2004, 2008; Rummel, 2007; Sechrest, 1999; Smith, 1979; Sneed, 1977; Spencer, 1970, 1981; Spooner, 1870; Strasnick, 1979; Stringham, Edward, 1998-1999, 1999, 2002, 2003, 2005a, 2005b, 2006, 2007; M. and L. Tannehill, 1984; Tinsley, 1998-1999; Wollstein, 1969; Woolridge, 1970.

(9.) Chappell, 1978; Coulson, 2008; Cox, 1998; Gatto, 2002A, 2002B, 2010; Goodman, et al, 2010; Liggio and Peden, 1978; National Assessment of Educational Progress. 2006; Postiglione, 1982; Rothbard, 2006; Young and Block, 1999.

(10.) For a libertarian class analysis, see Domhoff, 1967, 1971, 1998; Hoppe, 1990; Hughes, 1977; Kolko, 1963; Mises, 1978; Oppenheimer, 1975; Raico, 1977; Rockwell, 2001

(11.) Bergland, 1986; Hoppe, 1993; Huebert, 2010; Kinsella, 1995, 1996; Narveson, 1988 ; Nozick, 1973; Rothbard, 1973, 1978, 1982; Woolridge, 1970

(12.) There is a wealth of empirical evidence that demonstrates that when comparisons can be made, with regard to service performed by both the private and the public sectors, that the former is from 2-4 times more efficient. See on this: Adie, 1999, 1990a, 1990b; Ahlbrandt, 1973; Alston, 2007; Anderson and Hill, 1996; Bennett, 1980; Bennett and DiLorenzo, 1982, 1989, 197; Bennett, and Johnson, 1980; Blair, Ginsberg, and Vogel, 1975; Boardman and Vining, 1989; Borcherding, 1977; Borcherding, Burnaby, Pommerehne, and Schneider, 1982; Butler, 1985, 1986; Chapman, 2008; Clarkson, 1972; Crain and Zardkoohi, 1978; Davies, 1971, 1977; De Alessi, 1982; D'Souza, Bortolotti, Fantini, and Megginson. 2000; Dewenter, and Malatesta, 2000; Fitzgerald, 1989; Frech, 1976; Hanke, 1987a, 1987b, 1987c; Lindsay, 1976; Megginson and Netter, 2000, 2001; Monsen and Walters, 1983; Moore, S., 1987; Moore, T., 1990; Moore, and Butler, 1987; Poole, 1976; Priest, 1975; Savas, 1987, 1979, 1982, 2000; Vining, and Boardman. 1992; White, 1978.

(13.) Anderson and Hill, 1979; Block, 2007A, 2010A, forthcoming; DiLorenzo, 2010; Hasnas, 1995; Higgs, 2009; Hoppe, 2008; King, 2010; Kinsella, 2009; Long, 2004; Molyneux, undated; Murphy, 2005; Rothbard, 1973, 1998; Stringham, 2007; Tannehill, 1984; Tinsley, 1998-1999.

(14.) Block, 1972, 2002A, 2004, 2006, 2007B, 2008, 2009A, 2009B, Forthcoming A, Forthcoming, B, Block and Arakaky, 2008, Block and Barnett, 2008, D'Amico and Block, 2007

(15.) In games, there are necessarily winners and losers. E.g., poker, monopoly, football. In the market, all participants must benefit, at least in the ex ante sense, otherwise they would not buy, sell, rent, invest, etc.

(16.) For the case in favor of free trade, see: Block, Horton and Walker, 1998; Brandly, 2002; Brown, 1987; Friedman and Friedman, 1997; Johnsson, 2004; Landsburg, 2008; Murphy, 2004; Ricardo, 1821; Smith, 1776.

(17.) Rothbard, 1998; Bastiat, 1962.

(18.) Schumpeter (1942, 198) states: "The theory which construes taxes on the analogy of club dues or of the purchase of the services of, say, a doctor only proves how far removed this part of the social science is from scientific habits of mind."

(19.) See fn. 10, supra, and related text.

(20.) For a critique of unions, see Baird, 1990, 2000; Block, 1984, 1991, 1996A, 1996B, 2010B; Evans and Block, 2002B; Heldman, 1977; Heldman, Bennett and Johnson, 1981; Hutt, 1973, 1989; Petro, 1957; Reynolds, 1984, 1987, 2009; Schmidt, 1973; Shea, 2010; Rothbard, 1993.

(21.) Reagan employed magnificent libertarian rhetoric, but budgets rose when he was governor of California and President of the U.S.

(22.) For an analysis of the business cycle based on Austrian economics, see Garrison, 2001; Hayek, 1931; Mises, 1912, 1949; Rothbard, 1975, 1993; Woods, 2009.

(23.) Ditto for two neighborhoods in one city, say, Greenwich Village and the Upper West Side in New York City, let alone two families living on the same city block. Arrant nonsense.

(24.) If scarcity were ever to disappear from the human condition, an utter impossibility, then and only then would there be a lack of employment slots. But, then, we would not need them, as we would have everything we wanted without them.

(25.) On the Hoover New Deal, see Anderson, 2000, 2002; Bibeault, 2009; Block, 2002; Murphy, 2009A, 2009B, 2010A, 2010B 2011; Rothbard, 1963, 1966A, 1966B, 1972; Rockwell, 2008; Stolyarov, 2009; Thies, 2010; Thornton, 2010; Westley, 2005; Woods, 2009. On the issue of how Roosevelt extended and worsened the depression of the 1930s see Rothbard, 1963.

(26.) See Paul, 2010; Rothbard, 1983; Woods, 2009.

JOSHUA KATZ

jalankatz@gmail.com

Oxford Academy

MICHAEL CUNEO

mcuneo86@hotmail.com

Independent Scholar

WALTER E. BLOCK

wblock@loyno.edu

Loyola University-New Orleans
COPYRIGHT 2011 Addleton Academic Publishers
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2011 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Katz, Joshua; Cuneo, Michael; Block, Walter E.
Publication:Economics, Management, and Financial Markets
Article Type:Report
Geographic Code:1USA
Date:Jun 1, 2011
Words:11619
Previous Article:Trend following and expected return.
Next Article:Calendar anomalies: evidence from the Colombo Stock Exchange.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2020 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters