Printer Friendly

Noonan, Harold W. Frege: a Critical Introduction.

Key Contemporary Thinkers. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2001. viii + 244 pp. Cloth, 50.00 [pounds sterling]; paper, 14.99 [pounds sterling]--Noonan's book comprises, along with a substantial introduction, chapters on Frege's logic, his philosophy of arithmetic, his philosophical logic and his theory of meaning, among them covering all his principal contributions to philosophy. The exposition, while remaining throughout accessible to any nonspecialist reader with a reasonable background in analytical philosophy, is sympathetic but at the same time searching and critical, aimed both at deepening our understanding of the reasons that led Frege to his most important doctrines and of the connections between them, and at bringing out clearly the difficulties to which they give rise. After a brief but engaging account of Frege's life and career, Noonan's introductory chapter provides a helpful sketch of the origins and development of his leading ideas in their philosophical and mathematical context--Kant's thesis that mathematics, while a priori, must be synthetic and his associated insistence on the role of intuition; the emergence of non-Euclidean geometries; and the drive for rigor and the arithmetization of analysis by Augustine Cauchy, Karl Weierstrass, and others--followed by a concise overview of Frege's main contributions which serves as a useful background to their more detailed discussion in the chapters that follow.

Chapter 2 sets out, with the aid of well-chosen examples, some of the more serious shortcomings in logic as Frege found it, brings out the underlying mathematical motivation for his Begriffsschrift, and explains in detail Frege's replacement of the traditional subject-predicate analysis of sentences by his own more powerful and flexible function-argument analysis and the development of the quantifier-variable notation--essential to his solution of the problem posed by sentences involving multiple generality and other problems besetting the traditional logic of terms--which, along with his presentation of the first formalization of (higher-order) quantification theory, constituted a massive step forward in the development of modern mathematical logic. In chapter 3, Noonan furnishes a close commentary on the argument of Frege's Grundlagen, accurately summarizing its sharp, and for the most part devastating, critique of views on the nature of number and arithmetic to which Frege was opposed, before setting forth his own analysis of the concept of number and associated defense of his thesis that the laws of arithmetic are analytic. Noonan's discussion here admirably conveys a sense of the extent to which it is--Frege's own eventual abandonment of his logicism in the face of Russell's antinomy notwithstanding--very much a live and vigorously debated question whether a modified version of Frege's position may be defensible, by assigning a leading role to Hume's principle in place of Frege's explicit definition of number in terms of extensions. While not pretending to resolve this question, Noonan clearly explains the issues on which it turns and helpfully points the reader to relevant contemporary discussion.

Chapters 4 and 5, devoted respectively to Frege's philosophical logic and theory of meaning, critically expound the central ideas developed in three articles published in the space of two years--"Function and Concept" (1891), "On Sense and Reference," and "On Concept and Object" (both 1892). In them we find, in the present reviewer's opinion, one of the clearest and most insightful introductory discussions of these key works yet published, effectively putting the reader in touch with the fundamental issues and problems in Frege's thought which still, deservedly, form the focus of the best recent work in the field. Of particular value is Noonan's careful explanation of Frege's commitment to the thesis that sentences containing empty proper names must lack truth-value, even though (according to Frege) they may nevertheless express perfectly determinate thoughts. Implausible though it is, the commitment is inevitable, Noonan argues, given Frege's functional theory of predication together with his theses that the reference of a sentence is its truth-value and that of a singular term the object it designates. It best avoided, Noonan suggests, by departing from the name/bearer relation as the prototype for the notion of reference, and allowing that empty singular terrors may have a semantic value consisting precisely in the fact that they lack a designation. This would allow such sentences to have reference even though they contain nondesignating names, and so enable one to hold that they express thoughts, but false ones. An arguably better way out, not considered by Noonan, would be to grant that sentences containing empty names need not for that reason be meaningless, but deny that they have sense in Frege's technical sense of that word, that is, deny that they express thoughts at all.

In spite of several decades of first-rate scholarship, it is open to question whether there has, prior to the appearance of this book, been a reliable introduction to his work which goes deep enough to do justice to the power and subtlety of Frege's thought while remaining accessible to beginners or nonspecialists. Noonan's book is, without qualification, the best general critical introduction to Frege's work I have read.--Bob Hale, University of Glasgow.
COPYRIGHT 2002 Philosophy Education Society, Inc.
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2002 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Hale, Bob
Publication:The Review of Metaphysics
Article Type:Book Review
Date:Sep 1, 2002
Words:828
Previous Article:Marshall, John. Descartes's Moral Theory.
Next Article:Oben, Freda Mary. The Life and Thought of St. Edith Stein.

Terms of use | Copyright © 2018 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters