Printer Friendly

Mathematics as a Science of Patterns.

Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1997

Mark Colyvan School of Philosophy University of Tasmania

Structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics is the view that the proper subject matter of mathematics is the relationships between various kinds of mathematical entities, rather than the entities themselves. So, for instance, number theory is the study of [Omega]-sequences. The nature of the entities that constitute the [Omega]-sequences is irrelevant - what is important is the structure that is common to all [Omega]-sequences. There is something undeniably right about structuralism. Indeed the structuralist slogans, 'mathematical objects are places in structures' or, Michael Resnik's favourite, 'mathematics is the science of patterns', seem to reveal important insights into the nature of mathematics and its subject matter.

The real significance of structuralism, though, is in its ability to provide answers to some rather difficult problems in the philosophy of mathematics. For example, structuralism is able to explain why mathematicians are typically only interested in describing the objects they study up to isomorphism - for that is all that there is to describe. Structuralism is also able to explain why we're inclined to think that either all of the natural numbers exist or none of them exist - for the natural numbers, like other structures, come as a package. Most importantly, structuralism provides a neat and plausible response to both Frege's Julius Caesar problem (cf. 'The Concept of Number' in P. Benacerraf and H. Putnam (eds) [1983], Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings, 2nd edn, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press) and Paul Benacerraf's underdetermination problem ('What Numbers Could Not Be', also in Benacerraf and Putnam [1983]). According to structuralists, Julius Caesar can play the role of the number two, so long as Caesar has the appropriate relationships with other entities, and together they make up an [Omega]-sequence (with Caesar being the successor of the successor of the entity playing the zero role, of course). Similarly, either von Neumann's {[null set],{[null set]} or Zermelo's {{[null set]}} can play the role of the number two. According to the structuralist, however, neither Julius Caesar nor {[null set],{[null set]} nor {{[null set]}} is the number two, for the number two is no more and no less than a position in a structure.

Structuralism has had its fair share of supporters over the years too. These have included mathematicians of the calibre of Dedekind, Hilbert, and Poincare, and philosophers such as Quine and Benacerraf and (somewhat tentatively) Putnam. Few, however, have provided detailed defences of this position and even fewer have given clear articulations of exactly what it is that structuralists are committed to. It is for these reasons that Michael Resnik's and Stewart Shapiro's books are very welcome additions to the literature in the philosophy of mathematics. Resnik and Shapiro are two of the most prominent contemporary defenders of this important position and it is great to see their views collected together in monographs.

Despite its undeniable appeal and influential supporters, structuralism has not been without its problems. It's probably not too gross a generalization to say that the main problems that have faced structuralism have been concerned with lack of clarity. After all, the slogans used to describe the view are nothing but highly evocative metaphors. In particular, philosophers have wondered: What is a structure? By virtue of what do two systems display the same structure? What is the ontological status of the structure itself? What is the ontological status of the positions in the structure? Is structuralism a realist or anti-realist philosophy of mathematics? How do we have epistemic access to (apparently abstract) structures? All of these important questions which need to be properly addressed before structuralism can be taken to be a fully-fledged philosophy of mathematics. A great deal of the two books under discussion is devoted to answering these questions. Indeed, as we have come to expect from both Resnik and Shapiro, the discussions of these questions are clear, thoughtful, and for the most part (I found) rather convincing.

There is a great deal of similarity between Resnik's and Shapiro's views, so many of the above questions are answered along similar lines: both Resnik and Shapiro are mathematical realists - they both believe that mathematical entities exist independently of our knowledge of them and that mathematical statements are mind-independently true or false; they both agree that structuralism and realism are independent of one another; and they both provide essentially the same account of sameness of structure. Moreover, they both agree that a structuralist can make sense of identifying positions from different structures. (It is often claimed that structuralists cannot identify the natural number 2 with the real number 2 and the complex number 2 + 0i, since these are positions in different structures.) Resnik and Shapiro agree that there is good reason to think that 'two' refers to the same object irrespectively of the background structure. Shapiro claims that this is a matter of stipulation - there is no fact of the matter about trans-structural identifications.

Given so much agreement, it is worth noting that one of the issues on which Resnik and Shapiro differ is that old platonist bugbear, epistemology. Resnik's epistemology is essentially Quinean. He argues for mathematical realism by explicit appeal to indispensability considerations and employs the familiar Quinean doctrines of naturalism and holism. This is not to say, however, that Resnik has nothing to add to Quine's well-known views on how we come to gain knowledge of abstract mathematical entities. Resnik's attention to detail and sensitivity to the various arguments used to cast doubt on Quine's position has led to various clarifications, refinements and innovations. For instance, Resnik provides a new 'pragmatic' indispensability argument which appears to be quite distinct from the traditional Quine-Putnam version. Moreover, Resnik's

argument seems to avoid some of the recent attacks on the traditional argument, and as such it deserves careful attention by mathematical realists and non-realists alike.

As with Quine, Resnik postulates entities. He recognizes that such an approach appears to sit a little uneasily with realism:

Postulational approaches seem better suited to conventionalists, who may claim that we make truths, than to realists, who must hold that we can only recognize independently obtaining truths (p. 175).

He begins his attempt to quell this unease by distinguishing two different questions:

[W]e must separate the question of whether [our mathematical ancestors] were justified in positing mathematical objects from the question of whether they were justified in believing in the things they posited (p. 185).

The crucial question for the realist, of course, is the question about belief. Not surprisingly, Resnik claims that (most) beliefs about mathematical posits are justified, and they're justified by the role they play in simplifying and unifying both mathematical theory and our best physical theories. This marks the difference between mathematical posits and the posits of literary fiction. In short, we know about mathematical entities because we posit them and such positing helps simplify and unify our best theories.

Shapiro's epistemology, on the other hand, relies on less familiar devices (in epistemology at least): abstraction and implicit definition. At the lowest level he takes it as given that we are able to recognize structures, for otherwise we could not recognize all the different tokens of the English letter 'E', say. Moreover, such recognition involves abstraction. Recognizing natural-number structures is in principle no different. Shapiro claims that this certainly does not provide an account of mathematical pattern-recognition, but the phenomenon is no more mysterious than the general problem of pattern-recognition: '[i]n the end, we either demystify numbers or we mystify more mundane items' (p. 114).

Appeal to simple abstraction and similar techniques is limited - it will not give us cardinalities large enough for the higher reaches of set theory. Such cardinalities, however, are provided by a more 'speculative and problematic' (p. 129) technique. Shapiro argues that

grasping a [mathematical] structure and understanding the language of its theory amount to the same thing. There is no more to understanding a structure and having the ability to refer to its places than having the ability to use the language correctly (p. 137).

Thus, for Shapiro, 'language provides our epistemic access to mathematical structures' (p. 137).

My portrayal of Resnik's and Shapiro's respective epistemologies is obviously rather superficial, but I hope not misleading because of this. What I find interesting about their discussions here is that despite a great deal of consensus on other matters, epistemological concerns drive Resnik to a fairly modest realism - enough mathematical objects to service empirical science (and a bit more). Whereas Shapiro is driven to what may seem like a rather extravagant position in which every coherent structure is taken to be real. Although my own sympathies lie more with Resnik than with Shapiro, this is not the place to take up that issue. It is clear, however, that the role of epistemology in the philosophy of mathematics did not decline with the decline of the causal theory of knowledge.

So far I have been concerned largely with Resnik's and Shapiro's commitment to structuralism. Although structuralism is certainly the central thesis of both books, I do not wish to give the impression that that is all these two books are about. Both books touch on many interesting and important topics to which both authors make major contributions. For example, both books provide enlightening discussions of truth, realism and non-realism: Michael Resnik argues that mathematical realists need only be committed to an immanent conception of truth; and Shapiro provides a very nice survey of the various non-realist positions in the philosophy of mathematics that try to reduce ontology by invoking modality. Of course it's not possible to discuss these topics in any detail here, but I do wish to draw attention to the fact that both books make significant efforts to connect their central theses with other topics both within the philosophy of mathematics and further afield.

In summary, these two books are interesting, well written, and go a long way to alleviate the concerns that some philosophers have with mathematical structuralism. At the very least, Resnik and Shapiro have both provided clear, well-motivated accounts of their own influential versions of structuralism, and so these two books will no doubt serve as convenient starting points for all future discussions of structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics. Mathematics as a Science of Patterns and Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology are thus timely and important additions to contemporary philosophy of mathematics.
COPYRIGHT 1998 Oxford University Press
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 1998 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 
Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Title Annotation:Review
Author:Colyvan, Mark
Publication:The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science
Article Type:Book Review
Date:Dec 1, 1998
Words:1732
Previous Article:The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics and the Measurement Process.
Next Article:Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2018 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters