Printer Friendly

Criminal attempts.

B. Act Crimes, Result Crimes: How Courts Should Decide

The solution to our problem can be reached by recognizing that in cases like Decker, the defendant's intention differs from that of the paradigmatic attempter. As we will see, despite this difference, sometimes the defendant's intention commits him to all of the components of the completed crime, and sometimes it does not. Therefore, sometimes the defendant's intention suffices for the attempt, and sometimes it does not. In other words, the distinction crucial to the resolution of hard cases is a distinction in mental state; in some such cases, the defendant has the mens rea for attempt, and in others he does not. The Guiding Commitment View tells us what intention the attempter has: an intention that commits him to each of the components of the completed crime. So it seems likely that we will be able to draw a distinction between those solicitations that rise to the level of attempt and those that do not by distinguishing between those solicitations that are motivated by an intention that commits the defendant to all the elements of the solicited crime, and those that do not.

In hard solicitation-as-attempt cases like Decker, the defendant's relevant intention is not an intention to perform any act that would serve as the act element of the completed crime. Decker did not intend to point a gun at his sister and pull the trigger, for instance. But in all such cases, the defendant does intend that the solicited party act in some particular objectionable way: Decker intends that Holston kill his sister. A crucial question, then, for determining if the defendant's solicitation amounts to an attempt is as follows: under what conditions is an intention with that content sufficient for the intention required for the attempt?

The answer to this question turns on the distinction between "act" and "result" elements of crimes. There is a clear distinction between what we merely cause and what we do. To do is to cause, but to cause is not necessarily to do; sometimes we cause events that we are not active with respect to in the way that is required for action. A woman calls her dog from across the street. The dog runs to her and, much to the woman's horror, is crushed by a passing car. The woman caused the dog to be crushed, but she did not crush the dog. A particular event, such as a dog being crushed, is an act element of a crime if, and only if, three things need to be shown by the prosecution to establish that the defendant committed the offense: that the event occurred, that the defendant caused the event, and that the defendant was active with respect to it. It must be shown, that is, that the event occurred and was caused by the defendant in the way that qualifies it as his doing. By contrast, if the event is a result element, it needs only to be shown that the event occurred and that the defendant caused it; the defendant need not be shown to have been active with respect to it. Circumstantial elements of crimes are those conditions that need to be shown to have been present, but do not need to be shown either to have been caused by the defendant or to have been something with respect to which the defendant was active. (47)

The distinction between acts and results is both highly intuitive and difficult to specify with precision. When you walk into a room, you cause the temperature in the room to rise, but that is not something you do. Part of the difference between results and doings derives from facts about mental state. The things that you cause unwittingly, without any kind of prior awareness of even the possibility that you will cause them, are not things with respect to which you are active. However, intention is not required for activity; there are things that we do, but unintentionally. Further, prior awareness falling short of intention, such as awareness of significant risk, plus causation does not suffice for activity. Even if the woman, in the example just given, who calls her dog was aware of a risk that her dog would be crushed, it is not the case that she crushed her dog. In that case, what is missing is a kind of personal involvement in the crucial event--dirty hands--that is present when the event is one with respect to which the agent is active. The project of laying bare the conditions that underlie our intuitive judgments about the line between what we do and what we cause is one of the central projects of the philosophy of action. Ultimately, a proposed specification of the conditions that constitute this distinction is beholden to our intuitive judgments. To test such a proposal, we need to compare it to the verdicts that we make in ordinary contexts. We need to decide whether the events that an agent is active with respect to under the account are those that we would judge, in sober moments, to possess that extra something that we find in action and for which causation by itself is insufficient. Luckily, the law's sorting task--the task of sorting those who have committed crimes from those who have not--can be carried out to a large extent, even if not always, by appeal to the intuitive judgments to which a precise account would be beholden. We can move forward trusting that when the prosecution needs to show that a defendant was not just the cause of an event but was also active with respect to that event, juries will know activity when they see it, and will know also when it has not been shown.

Therefore, under the Guiding Commitment View, the precise intention needed for an attempt is a function of the classification of the elements of the completed crime as act, result, or circumstance. The Guiding Commitment View tells us that what a person has attempted is a function of what his intention committed him to. Only if the defendant's intention commits him to all that is involved in the completed crime has he attempted. But what is involved in the completed crime is in part a function of the classification of its various elements as act, result, or circumstance. If the completed crime includes the act of defacing property, then for attempt the defendant's intention must commit him to property being defaced, to causing property to be defaced, and to being active with respect to the defacement of the property. By contrast, if the completed crime includes the result of property being defaced, then the defendant's intention must commit him only to property being defaced, and to being the cause of that; it need not commit him to being active with respect to the relevant event.

While crimes have distinct act elements and result elements, the acts that the criminal law cares about are virtually always described by reference to their results. The California murder statute of relevance to Decker's crime, a statute that is perfectly typical of jurisdictions that have not adopted the Model Penal Code, reads, "Murder is the unlawful killing of a human being ... with malice aforethought." (48) Should we characterize this as a crime with the act element of killing or a crime with the result element of death? It is far from clear what the answer is to this question. (More on this below.) Still, it is natural to characterize it in the first way, given the appearance in the statute of the term "killing." So characterized, among the things that must be proven in a murder trial in California is not just that the defendant caused a death, but also that the defendant was active with respect to that death. By contrast, the Model Penal Code defines one form of "criminal mischief' like so: "A person is guilty of criminal mischief if he ... purposely or recklessly causes another to suffer pecuniary loss by deception or threat." (49)

Here it seems that the act element is deception or threat-a guilty defendant deceived or threatened another--while pecuniary loss is a result element. (50) A guilty defendant caused pecuniary loss, but it need not be the case that he was active with respect to the other's loss of money. For a defendant to be guilty of criminal mischief under the Model Penal Code, he must have caused another to be deceived or threatened while active with respect to that condition, and must have caused another to lose something of pecuniary value. But his activity with respect to the latter condition is irrelevant; it will be present in some guilty defendants, absent in others. The broker who, through deception, takes control of another's money and loses it is guilty of criminal mischief; the defendant is active with respect to both the deception and the loss in such a case. But the person who deceives another and thereby leads him to make an investment whereby the victim loses his own money has also committed the crime; such a person has committed criminal mischief even though the defendant is not active with respect to the loss of money.

The divide between act elements and result elements is not merely formal; it is of normative significance. It is something about which legislators ought to debate when defining a crime by statute. To criminalize the causation of a fetus's death, for instance, would be to criminalize a much larger number of acts than would be criminalized were the crime to require, instead, the killing of a fetus. If a defendant is at fault in a minor car accident with a pregnant woman that results in the death of the fetus, then he has certainly caused a fetus's death, but it is far less clear that he has killed a fetus. We can imagine cases in which activity with respect to an event is absent despite the fact that there is causation. Whether we want to criminalize such behavior under a particular statute will depend on our normatively significant goals in writing the statute and will influence what penalty we take to be appropriate for the crime we are defining. One, although not the only, relevant factor is this: when an event, like a fetus's death, figures into the description of the act required for the crime--when what is criminalized is "the killing of a fetus"--the mens rea requirement for the act and the result cannot be different. A person who recklessly kills a fetus is also reckless with respect to the death of the fetus. By contrast, when an act element is separately defined from the result element--when what is criminalized is, for instance, any act that "causes the death of a fetus"--then there is room for the mens rea with respect to the act and result to diverge; it is possible to intentionally run a red light and only negligently thereby cause a fetus's death. So the act-result distinction makes a difference to what is criminalized. Although it is a formal distinction, the act-result divide is a formal distinction of normative importance.

Some intentions commit one to causing a particular result and commit one to being active with respect to it. Others commit one only to causing it. Although it is an imperfect guide, we often register this difference by describing what the person intends either with the word "to" or, instead, with the word "that." An intention to buy milk constitutes a commitment to both milk being bought and to the buying of it being something one does, or is active with respect to. An intention that milk is bought constitutes a commitment to causing that, but no commitment to doing it oneself. Someone with the intention to buy milk might be prompted to take a trip to the store. Someone who intends that milk be bought might be prompted to put it on the list of things that her friend, and not she, is to buy later.

Under the Guiding Commitment View, a person has attempted a crime only if his intention commits him to each of the elements of the completed crime. So, if the completed crime includes a particular result, such as "pecuniary loss," it suffices that the attempter intend that there should be pecuniary loss. If the completed crime includes a particular act, such as "deception or threat," then it is necessary that the attempter intend to deceive or threaten; an intention that a victim should be deceived or threatened will not suffice.

This distinction is the key to understanding the conditions under which a solicitation is an attempt. Recall that in cases like Decker, the defendant does not intend that he act himself, but only that the solicited party perform an act that would serve as the act element of the completed crime. Under what conditions does this show that the defendant lacks the mens rea of attempt? The defendant's intention is sufficient for the mens rea of attempt when the event that the defendant intends the solicited party to cause is a result element of the completed crime, but his intention is insufficient for the mens rea of attempt if that event figures in the specification of an act element of the completed crime. This conclusion follows immediately from the account of the intention needed with respect to acts and results just offered.

So does Decker have the intention needed for an attempt to murder his sister? Since California's homicide law apparently provides that one must have killed another in order to have committed murder--thereby incorporating the other's death into the definition of an act element of the crime--the answer appears to be "no." Under such a statute, an attempt to murder requires an intention to kill, something that Decker lacks; his intention that his sister die is not enough for attempted murder under California law because it does not commit him to being active with respect to that result, and so does not commit him to killing anyone. However, consider the Model Penal Code's alternative definition of homicide: "A person is guilty of criminal homicide if he purposely, knowingly, recklessly or negligently causes the death of another human being." (51) Here the act element is left undescribed; any act at all could serve for the act element of the completed crime, even an act that was not a killing. The death of a human being is a result element of the crime. Under the Model Penal Code, all purposive or knowing--as well as some reckless--criminal homicides are classified as murders provided that they are not committed under extreme emotional distress. Therefore, a person should be able to try to commit murder, as defined by the Model Penal Code, by intending to perform some act and intending that another dies. Decker has these two intentions, for he intends to solicit Holston and intends that his sister die. Therefore, Decker has attempted a murder under the Model Penal Code's definition of that crime. (52)

A court faced with a statute that specifies "causing A" as an element must consider whether there is an appropriate verb that would have allowed "A-ing" instead of "causing A." If so, then that is a powerful reason to take A to be a result element. Consider, for instance, a statute prohibiting "causing the release of classified information." That the legislature did not instead prohibit "releasing classified information" is evidence that the information's release is a result rather than an act element of the crime. However, if there is no such verb, then the statute is ambiguous; agency can be present even when there is no relevant verb. Consider, for instance, a statute prohibiting "causing a wildfire." Since there is no verb "to wildfire," it is unclear whether the occurrence of the wildfire is an act or result element of the crime. In such a case, the court may have no choice but to ask whether the normatively relevant category of conduct is the one in which the agent is active with respect to the event, or the one in which he is merely the cause of it.

Conversely, when a court is faced with a statute that specifies "A-ing" as an element of the crime, but the legislature could just as easily have criminalized "causing A," that is one piece of evidence that the element in question is an act element. In the absence of a special reason to think the element is a result element, it should be classified as an act element. However, the fact that the legislature could have written the statute either way is a highly defeasible piece of evidence because legislatures are not as attuned to the distinction between acts and results as they should be and so may have intended the element in question to be a result while using an active verb to refer to it. In such cases, an argument showing that causing A is just as bad as--or just as legitimately criminalized as--A-ing will support the characterization of the element in question as a result element, despite the statutory language.

Although I will not defend the claim here, it seems to me that the Model Penal Code's definition of homicide (with the death of another as a result element rather than killing another as an act element) is superior, on normative grounds, to definitions, like that in California, under which a killing is apparently required--or, rather, in which such a requirement fits most naturally with the statute's language. (53) But the important point for our purposes is that the question of whether a solicitor has the intention needed for an attempt has to be settled by a normative argument over how to define the completed crime. One can imagine the Decker court's having reached the verdict it sought, even given the language of California's murder statute, by claiming that, despite appearances to the contrary, the death of another is a result element of the crime of murder in California. To do this, the court would have had to abandon the most natural interpretation of the explicit language of the statute, but there may be an argument for doing so. After all, the court might have reasoned, common law homicide definitions were formulated using language that was developed without the act-result distinction firmly in mind, and so it would be no surprise if some statutes were drafted with language misleadingly suggesting that a result element figures, instead, into the description of an act element. The fact that, on normative grounds, it is arguably better for death to be considered a result strengthens the case for this form of argument.

C. Taking Stock

In attempt and solicitation, not to mention conspiracy, we recognize a sense in which the criminality of the act is diluted in comparison to that from which its criminality derives, namely the completed crime attempted or solicit ed. If completed crimes are blood red, then attempts and solicitations seem to be shades of pink. This metaphor tempts one to imagine that the more we stack attempts and solicitations on top of one another, and the more attenuated the relation to the completed crime becomes, the more diluted is the criminal liability. However, this is only a metaphor and one by which we should not be misled. In attempted crimes we do what we can to extend our agency into the world in objectionable ways. In solicitations, we do what we can to extend another's agency into the world in objectionable ways. What has been shown in this Part is that one way to extend one's own agency into the world is to lead another to extend his. This is so when all that is required to extend one's own agency into the world in an objectionable way is to cause a result. In order to try to cause a result, it is enough to ask another to bring it about. Others cannot act for us, but they can alter the world on our behalf, and sometimes to ask someone to do so is enough to try to do so oneself.

It is important to see how the idea that solicitation rises to the level of attempt in result crimes, and not in act crimes, derives from the theoretical framework developed in Parts I, II, and III. Under the Transfer Principle, the prohibition of an action is also an implicit prohibition of an attempt to engage in that action; a prohibition of causing a result is an implicit prohibition of an attempt to cause that result. (54) Either way, the prohibited attempt is of the sort that would count as an attempt under the Guiding Commitment View. This type of prohibited attempt, in turn, requires an intention that commits one to that which is involved in completion. If completion involves an act, then the attempt requires an intention that commits one to three things: an event's occurrence, being the cause of it, and being active with respect to it. An intention that a solicited party act in the prohibited way does not commit the defendant to being active with respect to that which the solicited party is asked to cause. Therefore, the defendant is not, in such a case, attempting to engage in the prohibited conduct in the sense of relevance to criminal law; he lacks an intention-based commitment as required for the attempt. By contrast, if what is prohibited is the causing of an event, then the defendant has attempted only if he has an intention that commits him to the event's occurrence and commits him to causing it. He can be so committed by an intention that a solicited party cause the event. He therefore may have an intention that suffices for the attempt. The conception of attempt on offer in this Article, that is, provides us with principled grounds on which to resolve hard solicitation-as-attempt cases of a sort that have baffled the courts.

V. CIRCUMSTANCES AND "IMPOSSIBILITY"

A. Clearing Ground and Setting Aside Legal and Factual Impossibility

There is perhaps no area of criminal law in which there is more confusion, on the parts of both courts and commentators, than in the adjudication of so-called "impossible" attempts. Consider an appealing line of thought that leads to a disastrous set of doctrines, namely the doctrines employing the distinction between "legal" and "factual" impossibility. Start with cases sometimes dubbed as "pure legal impossibility" cases: a married man tries to commit adultery and fails. The object of his affections is not interested. Ashamed and falsely believing that adultery is illegal, he runs to his local police station to turn himself in for attempted adultery. The police laugh in his face and send him home. Why? Because: it is not a crime to attempt to do something that would not be criminal were you to have done as intended. Had the attempted adulterer succeeded, he would have committed no crime, and so his attempt was no crime. So far so good. Or so it seems.

But now let's extend that principle. Consider a case that has occupied the imagination of many a criminal law theorist, namely People v. Jaffe. (55) The defendant, who was suspected of regularly aiding thieves by selling the goods they took, was charged with an attempt to receive stolen property after he purchased some fabric that he believed to be stolen (56) but that was in fact falsely represented to him as stolen as part of a sting operation. (57) At least part of what Jaffe intended was to receive property. But in fulfilling that intention, Jaffe did not commit a crime, because the property he intended to receive was not stolen. Apply the principle appealed to in the case of the attempted adulterer, and it appears to follow that Jaffe has not attempted receipt of stolen property. In both cases, that is, the defendant has an intention such that, were it fulfilled (and in Jaffe's case it actually was fulfilled), there would be no crime. Now, if Jaffe did not attempt receipt of stolen property, then attempt liability radically shrinks, as do the tools available to law enforcement. In order to avoid this outcome, judges sought a distinction between a case like that of the attempted adulterer and a case like Jaffe. It is not implausible to think that what distinguishes the cases is that the attempted adulterer made a mistake of law, while Jaffe made a mistake of fact. Hence a bit of doctrine is born: if the obstacle to completion is factual, the attempt is criminal (the case is one of "factual impossibility"), while if the obstacle is legal, the attempt is not criminal (the case is one of "legal impossibility").

But the doctrine is a disaster, and, thankfully, has almost disappeared in the United States. The problems are many and need not be rehearsed here. (58) What is of importance to us is a subtle error that leads to the doctrine, an error that we must not make in thinking about cases like Jaffe. The reason that the attempted adulterer has committed no crime is that he is not committed by his intention to all of the components of any crime. He is committed, instead, to the components of a non-criminal form of conduct, namely adultery. The mistake is in thinking that the right question to ask is, "Would the attempted adulterer have committed a crime had he done as intended?" This is the wrong question because it invites an answer in which we appeal to facts about the world to which the defendant is not committed by his intention--namely any facts that would be in place were he to do as intended. Recall the "wide" sense of trying, discussed in Part I, under which any facts about what the person would do were he to do as he intends--including facts about whether his conduct would be criminal--can be appealed to in a description of what he is trying to do. To explain why the attempted adulterer has committed no crime by appealing to the fact that he would not have committed a crime had he done as intended is to assume that the sense of "try" that informs the criminal law is the "wide" sense, rather than the sense defined under the Guiding Commitment View. Accepting such an explanation of the non-criminality of the attempted adulterer's conduct would be to invite mistake in the treatment of a case like Jaffe. The right question to ask about Jaffe is not "Would he have committed a crime had he done as intended?"--a question to which the answer is "no." The right question is, "Was he committed by his intention to all of the components of the crime of receipt of stolen property?"--a question to which the answer may be "yes" (for reasons to be explained below). We need to at tend not to what would be the case were the defendant to do as intended, but to that to which he is committed by his intention.

This change in orientation radically alters the problem. The important issue not only has nothing to do with the fact-law distinction, but also has nothing to do with impossibility. Sometimes we are committed by our intentions to things that cannot come to pass, sometimes to things that can. What is crucial is what we are committed to, not whether it can come to pass. The next step is to remember that, as emphasized in Part II, a person can be committed by his intention to a condition without being committed to promoting that condition. We can also be committed to not reconsidering our intention in light of the presence of the condition, and thanks to an intention, we can be committed to not complaining that the world is in a certain condition. When we have these forms of commitment, we are under no pressure to adopt necessary means to realizing the condition to which we are committed. Under the Guiding Commitment View, when a person is not committed to promoting a condition, but is committed to it in one of these other two ways, then the condition can be appealed to in a characterization of what he is trying to do. So if it were the case that Jaffe was committed in one of these ways by his intention to the property being stolen, then he attempted receipt of stolen property in the sense that is criminalized under the Transfer Principle. Was he?

B. Belief and the Rebuttable Presumption

It is obvious that in a case like Jaffe a crucial fact about the defendant that informs our belief that he attempted a crime is that he believed that the property he received was stolen. Similarly, recall that Crow believed that the person he tried to sexually exploit, "StephieFL," was a minor. And there are many other cases with the same structure. Not all such cases have led to conviction for attempt, even though that is by far the most common result. (59) In United States v. Berrigan, (60) for instance, the defendant thought that he was smuggling letters out of the prison in which he was housed without the warden's knowledge. (61)

In fact, the warden knew all about it and was allowing the letters to leave so as to help the police track the activity outside the prison that Berrigan was directing through the letters. (62) The court acquitted Berrigan of the attempt to smuggle letters out without the warden's knowledge on the ground that the presence of the circumstantial element of the completed crime (namely that the warden did not know) was required for the attempt. (63) If this seems like the wrong result in this case, it is at least in part because Berrigan believed the warden did not know of the letters. The defendant's belief seems to matter, but why?

One might think that any view, such as the Guiding Commitment View, that requires for attempt an intention-based commitment to each of the conditions involved in the completed crime must say that belief is insufficient in cases like Jaffe, Crow, and Berrigan. After all, it is common to believe a condition to be in place without it being something to which one is committed by one's intention. The runner believes that he lives in Los Angeles, but we cannot infer from this fact, together with the fact that he intends to go running, the further claim that he intends to go running in Los Angeles. That is something that he takes for granted, not something that he directs his will toward in the form of an intention. Perhaps it is like that with Jaffe, or Crow, or Berrigan. Perhaps they believe that the relevant conditions are in place, without those conditions being things to which they are committed by their intentions.

And indeed this is possible. It is just extremely unlikely. There are quite complicated principles that govern the flow of information from one mental state to another; sometimes content bleeds from one mental state to another, and sometimes it does not. Often, people who believe that Obama is Hawaiian and believe that Obama is President also believe that a Hawaiian is President. But a particular person might not have this further belief. He might not "put two and two together." If asked if a Hawaiian has ever been President, he might have to think about it, or he might even answer "no" before realizing that this conflicts with an implication of other things that he believes. Failures to put two and two together have two related sources of importance. First, we sometimes fail to put two and two together because one belief or the other is buried; it is not "before the mind" in the way that it would need to be to serve as a premise in reasoning through which its content would bleed into the other. This might be the case for someone who knows that Obama is Hawaiian but has not given that any thought in some time. Second, and alternatively, a person can fail to put two and two together because one of the facts is extremely unimportant to him; it is not salient. Someone who doesn't care about such things will not have the thought that the President is a dog owner, even if he has the thought that Obama is a dog owner, and the thought that Obama is President.

These examples involve pairs of beliefs, but we find the same limitations on content moving from a belief to an intention. Someone who intends to vote for Obama might not intend to vote for a dog owner, even though he knows that Obama is a dog owner. That fact just does not matter to him. Or even if it does matter to him, it might not be before his mind at the time that he intends to vote for Obama. But notice how rare it is in criminal cases like Jaffe, Crow, and Berrigan for either the relevant beliefs to be buried or for the conditions not to be salient to the defendant. The relevant conditions are labeled as parts of crimes, which itself makes them salient in the minds of many people. Furthermore, in many cases they are labeled as such because they are morally important. And even many of those with radically different moral views from those enshrined in criminal law recognize that the prospect of punishment is linked to the presence or absence of the relevant conditions, and that, for most, makes the conditions salient. This is not to say that there are no defendants in whom the beliefs are buried or the conditions not salient; there undoubtedly are, but they are rare. They are rare enough for the fact of belief in the relevant condition to provide a rebuttable presumption that the condition is included in the content of the defendant's intention. Given that he believes that the property is stolen and intends to receive property, we can be virtually certain that Jaffe intends to receive stolen property; given that he believes that StephieFL is thirteen and that he intends to sexually exploit her, we can be virtually certain that Crow intends to sexually exploit a minor; given that he believes the warden is ignorant of his activities and that he intends to send letters, we can be virtually certain that Berrigan intends to send letters without the warden's knowledge. Can we be certain that the relevant conditions bleed from the defendants' beliefs to their intentions? It is not a conceptual truth, but in the absence of evidence that defeats the claim, there is every reason to think the intention includes a representation of the believed condition.

So if we ask, "What is the appropriate mens rea standard in attempt with respect to the circumstantial elements of the completed crime?" the answer is "intent." That is an implication of the Guiding Commitment View that we should embrace. But mental states "lower" on the mens rea hierarchy can provide extremely good evidence, sufficient evidence in the absence of rebuttal, for the needed intention. If there are remaining intuitions that intent is too high a standard in this domain, then they arise from a failure to appreciate the fact that one can intend a condition, and thereby be committed to it, without having any commitment to promote it. To say that Crow intends to sexually exploit a minor is not to say that he would have dropped his pursuit of her photographs had he discovered she was not a minor. Maybe he would have been happy to receive sexually explicit pictures of either a minor or an adult. Who knows? But still, given that he intended to sexually exploit a minor, he was committed to her being a minor in both the senses of non-reconsideration and non-complaint. He could not rationally have changed his mind on encountering further evidence of her minor status; nor could he complain that the world came out differently from the way he intended if, in the end, he sexually exploited a minor. These are commitments that he incurs compatible with the absence of any commitment on his part to see to, or promote, the object of his sexual exploitation's being a minor. And it is thanks to the fact that he has these intention-based commitments that he is properly said to have attempted to sexually exploit a minor in the sense of relevance to criminal law.

C. Recklessness and the Relevance of the Facts

Cases in which the defendant believes the relevant circumstantial element of the completed crime to be present are not, by any means, the only sort. A defendant who tries to take something that he lacks permission to take might fall short of belief that he lacks permission; perhaps he is merely reckless in this respect--his wife was supposed to ask permission for him to take his neighbor's car, but he's not sure if she remembered. His belief is aptly characterized as probabilistic, rather than "flat-out." He does not flat-out believe that he lacks permission; he believes, instead, that there's a decent chance he lacks permission. Did such a defendant attempt theft? A defendant who tries to buy a stereo off the back of a truck falls short of belief that the stereo is stolen--maybe it's just a roaming garage sale-but he knows there's a good chance that it is. Did such a defendant attempt to receive stolen property?

Notice that these recklessness cases are importantly different from those involving defendants who are negligent or even blamelessly oblivious to the presence of certain conditions. In negligent attempts, there is no mental state the content of which can bleed into the content of the intention. Hence there is no intention-based commitment to the relevant condition. This is why it is just false to say that someone who tries to have sex with someone underage, but whom he unreasonably believes to be an adult, has attempted rape. This is false even if negligence, or less, will suffice for the completed crime. When it comes to the attempt, we need intention-based commitment. Furthermore, when there is no mental representation of the relevant condition, there is no such commitment.

Under the Guiding Commitment View, the question in recklessness cases, by contrast to negligence cases, is parallel to the question involved in the flat-out belief cases: is the defendant committed to the condition (that he lacks permission, that the property is stolen) by his intention? If so, then we can appeal to the condition in describing what he is trying to do (steal rather than merely take; receive stolen property); and if not, then we cannot. To a point, although only to a point, the solution is the same as well: the content of the probabilistic belief can be presumed to bleed into the content of the intention in the absence of a failure on the defendant's part to put two and two together. However, there is an important difference. When the content of the probabilistic belief bleeds into the content of the intention, the defendant does not intend to receive stolen property, but instead intends to receive possibly stolen property. So we have a new question: does an intention-based commitment to the property's possibly being stolen suffice for the kind of commitment to its being stolen that is needed for attempt to receive stolen property?

The answer is, for reasons to be explained, that it suffices only if the property is actually stolen. In short, whether the intention to receive possibly stolen property constitutes a commitment to the property's being stolen depends on whether it is, in fact, stolen. To see this, start by noticing that an intention to receive possibly stolen property does not generate a commitment of non-reconsideration with respect to the property's being stolen. A person with that intention whose doubt is removed--the guy on the back of the truck, for instance, says, "By the way, this stuff is hot"--could rationally reconsider his intention in light of the newly formed belief that the property is stolen. A rational agent might be willing to go through with the purchase when he's not certain and unwilling to go through with it when he is. So, if the intention to receive possibly stolen property commits one to its being stolen, it cannot be because it generates a commitment of non-reconsideration.

What about a commitment to not complaining? Here there are conditions under which the intention in question generates such a commitment. Say, for instance, that the stereo is purchased and the purchaser is arrested, and it is demonstrated that the stereo is stolen. Can the purchaser rationally deflect criticism from himself by noting that at least the world is not in a condition he intended it to be in? No, for the intention depicts the property as stolen, with some degree of likelihood, and unstolen with some other degree of likelihood. Given that the property is in fact stolen, the intention's depiction of the property's status is accurate; the intention matches the world. If you think the world might be a certain way, and it is that way, then you were right. If you think the world might be one of two ways, and it turns out to be one of them, then you were right. Similarly, if an intention depicts the world as possibly a certain way, and the world is that way, then the intention matches the world.

Since it would be irrational for the defendant to insist that the stereo's being stolen is something he did not intend, he has a commitment of non-complaint with respect to the property's being stolen. But notice: he only has that commitment if the property is actually stolen. If the property turns out not to be stolen, then that is something that he is committed to not complaining about. What he is committed to not complaining about is a function of how things are. What follows is that when the defendant is merely reckless with respect to the relevant condition, he has attempted the crime only if the condition is actually in place. So, whether the prosecution bears a burden to show that the condition is in place depends on what the defendant's mental state is. If the defendant believes the condition to be in place, then the prosecution bears no such burden. But if the defendant is merely reckless with respect to the condition, then the prosecution must establish that the condition is in place in order to establish that the defendant attempted the crime. Put conversely: when the prosecution is able to prove only that the defendant was reckless with respect to a particular circumstance, then the prosecution must also prove that the circumstance was in place in order to show that the defendant attempted the crime.

One of the things that is uncovered here is the root of a particular source of confusion in the conceptualization of attempt. We recognize, and without difficulty, that when it comes to a completed crime like receipt of stolen property, there are two different and separable questions to ask. First: was the property stolen? Second: did the defendant believe that the property was stolen? There are two questions because there are two different morally salient facts: one about the property's status and another about the mental state of the defendant with respect to that fact. But when theorists have tackled cases of "impossible" attempt--cases like Jaffe, Crow, or Berrigan, or equivalent cases involving recklessness rather than knowledge--the question of whether the circumstances need to be in place has seemed to be inextricably intertwined with the question of what the defendant's mental attitude needs to be toward the circumstance.

The result is that the opposite sides of the bar talk past each other. One side sees the import of the circumstantial facts, the other of the mental state--and it can seem as though adjudicating the dispute requires deciding which of the two matters, to the neglect of the other.

But there is a reason why the facts and the defendant's mental state with respect to them seem entwined in attempt: they are entwined in attempt. When the defendant's intent is, for instance, to sexually exploit someone who might be a minor, he is attempting to sexually exploit a minor only if the victim is in fact a minor. The facts are relevant to what his mental state commits him to. What his mental state commits him to is relevant to what he is trying to do in the sense of relevance to the criminal law. And what he is trying to do in that sense is relevant to whether he has committed a criminal attempt, because we criminalize attempts under the Transfer Principle. The abstract bit of progress made here in philosophy of mind and action--noting the range of commitments beyond commitments of promotion--is not merely that; instead, it is identifying something about which those who care about crime and culpability ought to care.

D. Taking Stock

In our resolution of the problem of solicitation-as-attempt, we needed to appeal to the Guiding Commitment View and to a plausible theory of the distinction between result and act elements of crimes. Only one implication of the Guiding Commitment View mattered to the analysis: where we find the kind of trying that matters to criminal responsibility, we also find an intention that commits the agent to each of the conditions involved in completion. The problem of solicitation-as-attempt did not require appeal to the distinction, developed in Part II, among the three different types of intention-based commitment, namely commitments of promotion, non-reconsideration, and noncomplaint.

However, our resolution of the problem of "impossibility" in this Part has indeed required appeal to that tripartite distinction. A failure to appreciate that there are ways to be committed to a condition that do not amount to commitments of promotion can lead one to the mistaken conclusion that intent is too high a mens rea standard with respect to circumstantial elements in attempt. This failure can lead one to the conclusion, that is, that attempt does not require intention-based commitments to each of the elements of the crime attempted; the circumstantial elements, at least, are exempted. But the recognition that there are indeed forms of intention-based commitment that fall short of commitments of promotion allows us to see something new: the Guiding Commitment View's implication that attempt requires intent (even with respect to circumstantial elements of completion) is not just unproblematic, but in fact allows for an insight. It allows for the recognition that sometimes what your intentions commit you to is partly a matter of what is in fact the case.

In short, it is because of the tripartite division among types of intention-based commitment that it is defensible to view intent as the appropriate mens rea standard with respect to circumstances in attempt. That tripartite division also leads to the conclusion that a rebuttable presumption of mens rea is generated by both (a) belief that the circumstance is in place or (b) recklessness with respect to the circumstance when, in fact, the circumstance is in place.

VI. ABANDONMENT AND CHANCE OF MIND

Recall how we got here. We started with the idea of the Transfer Principle: attempts are crimes because they are implicitly prohibited in our prohibitions of completed crimes. This insight provided us with a constraint on an account of what, exactly, attempts are in the legally relevant sense: they must be such as to inherit their criminality from completion. This constraint, in turn, led to the formulation of the Guiding Commitment View, an account of attempt that is both intuitively appealing and supports the result that attempts are implicitly prohibited whenever completions are. The Guiding Commitment View, informed as it is by recent work on intention, allows principled resolution of the problems of solicitation-as-attempt and (so-called) "impossibility." But as we will see in this Part, the Transfer Principle allows for resolution of at least one thorny problem about attempt, namely the problem of abandonment, even without appeal to the Guiding Commitment View and its associated theory of the nature of the commitments constituted by our intentions. The Transfer Principle, that is, is independently fruitful. Just by recognizing that the reasons for criminalizing attempt all derive from the reasons for criminalizing completion --an implication of the Transfer Principle--we are able to see under what conditions abandonment is relevant to criminal responsibility for attempt, and how.

A. The Problem

Consider Arin Ahmed, a Palestinian who tried to kill a number of Jews in a public place through a suicide bombing but changed her mind before the plan was complete. (64) Here is how Ahmed describes how it came to pass that she stopped herself before anyone was hurt:
   I got out of the car.... I saw a lot of people, mothers with
   children, teenage boys and girls. I remembered an Israeli girl my
   age whom I used to be in touch with. I suddenly understood what I
   was about to do and I said to myself: How can I do such a thing? I
   changed my mind. (65)


There is no doubting the prevalence and strength of the intuition that someone like Ahmed is importantly different, and ought to be treated differently under the law, from someone who got out of the car intent on a suicide bombing and was wrestled to the ground by police before any damage could be done. The fact of change of mind seems intuitively to be of tremendous ethical importance to responsibility for attempt. In fact, the Model Penal Code gives expression to this idea in its affirmative defense of abandonment. Under Model Penal Code [section] 5.01(4), a person who abandons an attempt (under certain conditions that appear to be met in Ahmed's case) has an affirmative defense from the charge. (66) Twenty-six jurisdictions in the United States follow the Model Penal Code approach in allowing an affirmative defense of abandonment, (67) and some commentators who oppose it favor, instead, granting mitigation rather than a complete defense to those who, like Ahmed, abandon their attempts for laudatory reasons. (68) It is very hard these days to find anyone defending the common law position that abandonment is of no relevance to guilt for attempt. Even judges in jurisdictions that have never granted a defense or mitigation on the basis of abandonment tend to avoid asserting that none is to be granted as a matter of law in their jurisdictions. For instance, while there is officially no abandonment defense in federal law, federal judges faced with the question tend to do their best to avoid the issue by claiming that even if abandonment were a defense or provided mitigation, the defendant before them provided insufficient evidence of abandonment. (69) In fact, we see this even in cases in which the evidence of abandonment would likely suffice for defense or mitigation in a jurisdiction that explicitly recognizes defense or mitigation in cases of abandonment.

Moral intuition (not to mention legal codes, like Model Penal Code [section]5.01(4)) supports the further idea that the defendant's motive for abandoning his attempt is of crucial importance to the question of whether to punish the defendant or to reduce his punishment. To give the most obvious example, a defendant who abandons his attempt because he discovers that if he goes through with the crime he will be caught--perhaps a police car happens to be passing by unexpectedly--does not deserve a defense or mitigation. After all, he is in no better a moral position than the defendant who is stopped through frank physical force by the police; the fact that he stops himself is irrelevant. There are other examples, too. A defendant who stalks a victim intending a robbery, but decides to wait until later to complete it when he comes to believe that if he waits he can commit the robbery after the victim has visited an ATM, does not deserve a defense or mitigation. Broadly speaking, we recognize various impure motives for abandoning--motives importantly different from Ahmed's motives--that undermine whatever mitigating force the abandonment has. But why is this? Whatever rationale we give for granting a defense or mitigation on the basis of abandonment must support the idea that the motive for abandonment matters; a bad motive for abandoning can undermine abandonment's mitigating force.

In addition to accounting for the fact that the motive for abandoning matters, a principled account of how the courts should respond to abandoned attempts must be consistent with the fact that abandonment of the kind that is puzzling happens after the defendant has attempted a crime. To be sure, there are cases in which the defendant abandons before he's even tried to commit the crime; imagine the person who intends to rob a bank, has a hearty breakfast in preparation, and then changes his mind. But the explanation for why criminal penalties are inappropriate in cases like that does not appeal to the fact of change of mind. Instead, it points to the fact that the defendant has not done enough, or has not done the right kind of thing, to count as having attempted the crime at all. (70) The cases where special conceptual resources are needed are those in which the defendant has committed an attempted crime but changed his mind before completing it. In this way, abandonment sits in the same temporal relation to the charged crime as remorse: it happens after that which we take to be criminal. But abandonment of attempt seems to many people to be relevant to responsibility in some way that is entirely different from the way in which remorse is relevant. (No jurisdiction offers an affirmative defense of remorse, not even those that offer an affirmative defense of abandonment.) This must be explained by an adequate account of the relevance of abandonment to responsibility for attempt.

One initially appealing account of the relevance of abandonment is incapable of accounting for some of its central features. Consider the claim that we give those who abandon a punishment discount--100% off under the Model Penal Code, which allows an affirmative defense--in order to incentivize abandonment. (71) Since the police can't stop everyone, we want to give people incentives to stop themselves. So we want someone who has attempted a crime to see that he has not thereby earned himself the punishment for completion; he can still avoid that punishment by abandoning. There are two problems with this line of thought: first, in a regime in which failed attempts are punished less heavily than completions, as is the case for the vast majority of crimes in the vast majority of jurisdictions in the United States, defendants already have incentives to abandon; by abandoning, they can avoid the enhanced penalty for completion. This implies that it is at least an open empirical question whether any more attempts are abandoned in a regime that allows mitigation or an affirmative defense for abandonment than are abandoned thanks to the punishment discount for falling short of completion. Second, and more importantly, this rationale is not available to those who think, as they should, that abandonment mitigates only when it is motivated in the right way. Someone who is motivated to abandon by the prospect of a punishment discount is not properly motivated. (72) Such a person is really no different from one who abandons because he thinks if he follows through he will be caught. So this intuitively appealing aspect of legal doctrine cannot be explained in its entirety by appeal to the hope to incentivize abandonment.

How is it best explained? As we will see, the best explanation implies that abandonment ought to mitigate a defendant's sentence but ought not provide an affirmative defense.

B. Mitigating Factors and the Ceiling on Attempt's Sanction

The right way to think of the relevance of abandonment arises from appreciating the grounds for the following undeniable fact: it is illegitimate to punish a failed attempt more heavily than it would have been punished had it been completed. This is not to say that there are no attempted murders, for instance, that are rightly sanctioned more heavily than some completed murders. Rather, it is to say that no attempted murder is rightly sanctioned more heavily than that very murder would have been rightly sanctioned had it been completed. The best rationale for this is that every reason to sanction attempt is a reason to sanction completion, even if there are additional reasons to sanction completion that are not reasons to sanction attempt. Only if there were reasons to sanction attempt that were not reasons to sanction completion would it be acceptable to give a greater penalty to an attempt than to completion of that attempt. It is an implication of the fact that attempts are criminalized under the Transfer Principle that there can be no reasons to punish an attempt that are not reasons to punish completion of that attempt. So the appealing idea that the punishment for completion sets the ceiling for the punishment of attempt is an implication of the Transfer Principle.

The fact that reasons for sanctioning attempt are all reasons for sanctioning completion of the attempt also implies that many mitigating factors for the sentence for completion are also mitigating factors for the sentence for attempt. Seeing this requires recognizing that often a factor mitigates thanks to the fact that it silences a reason for sanctioning. If a reason for sanctioning completion is silenced by the presence of a mitigating factor, and the silenced reason is also in general a reason for sanctioning attempt, then the mitigating factor also mitigates sentence for attempt. I explain.

Mitigating and aggravating factors are never decisive. When such a factor is present, there is a reason for issuing a lower or higher sentence, or one fewer reason not to; the reasons in question rarely settle the question of what sanction to give. Hence a mitigating factor could be present and yet it might make sense to give the defendant a greater than typical sentence because there are several aggravating factors present also. Similarly, a mitigating factor might be present, but there may be a reason for sanctioning that is in no way lessened by the presence of the mitigating factor and which supports issuing a sanction of typical size. In such cases, a mitigating factor is present but makes no difference to the final sentence. In this way, mitigating and aggravating factors are importantly different from either justifications or excuses. When a defendant has a justification--he injured another in the execution of a public duty, for instance--that settles the matter against punishment of the defendant. (73) We do not weigh the justification against, for instance, the suffering of the victim, or the dangerousness of the defendant; a justification deflects criminal liability entirely. Similarly with excuse. Mitigating and aggravating factors, however, are different. They merely figure into the calculus of reasons for sanction and are therefore subject to all the vicissitudes of reasons; they can be present without changing the outcome, or absent even when the outcome is to be changed.

Affirmative defenses, note, are all-or-nothing. When they are present, they shield a defendant completely from criminal liability. This is why they are a useful legislative tool for providing justified and excused defendants with what they deserve. If a defendant acts in self-defense, for instance, the best way to give him what he deserves is to provide him with a way of avoiding criminal liability altogether. But an affirmative defense is the wrong tool to use when the facts in question mitigate; to grant an affirmative defense when a mitigating factor is present is to provide defendants more than they deserve, for mitigating factors, by their nature, can be outweighed, at least potentially, by other, aggravating factors. The conception of a factor as having some degree of weight, and thus possibly being outweighed, is not available with an affirmative defense.

Mitigating factors (and perhaps aggravating factors, too) can potentially function in at least two importantly different ways. First, they can provide positive support for giving a lower sanction. Considerations of mercy function in this way. If giving a lower sanction would be merciful, and if there are reasons to be merciful, then there is a positive reason to give a lower sanction than would otherwise be appropriate. Second, and more important for our purposes here, mitigating factors can cancel the force of a reason to give a particular sanction (say, a typical sanction) rather than a lower one. For instance, if the fact that a crime was the defendant's first offense mitigates at all, it mitigates in this way. (74) Sometimes a reason in support of issuing a particular sanction rather than a lower one is the fact that the behavior punished is part of a pattern of criminal conduct by the defendant. This reason--if it is one--for issuing a particular sanction rather than a lower one is muted by the fact that the defendant's crime was not part of a pattern at all. It will be argued here that abandonment mitigates in this second way.

C. Why Abandonment Mitigates

Judges should and do pursue multiple goals in sentencing. They ought to seek to deter the defendant from future crime, whether in or out of prison. They ought to have their eye on the deterrence of other people besides the defendant. Furthermore, they ought to consider whether the sanction is sufficient to express solidarity with the victim in his loss. They ought to consider what the defendant deserves and his prospects for, and need for, fundamental rehabilitative change. There is more besides. But there is one particular goal that, it will be argued, is of relevance to our discussion here: judges ought to pick the minimum sanction that would provide, by the defendant's own standards at the time of the crime, a sufficient reason for him to have refrained. That is, one of the things a judge should aim to do in sentencing is to give a sanction harsh enough that, had the defendant anticipated it at the time of the crime, he would have recognized sufficient reason to refrain. (More on this in a moment.) In general, however, judges have reason to give the lowest sanction that is supported by this and other reasons for sanctioning. That is, if there is just as good a reason to issue one sanction as another, then there is an additional reason to issue the lower of the two. Putting these two things together, we reach the result that, if knowing that he would suffer a year in prison would have prompted the defendant to recognize sufficient reason to refrain, then that is a reason to give a year rather than a year and a day. Conversely, if anticipation of a year would not have been sufficient to prompt awareness of sufficient reason to refrain, then there is reason to give a higher sanction.

When a defendant has abandoned an attempt for good reasons, he has already recognized sufficient reason not to complete the crime without anticipation of any sanction. Therefore, when the defendant has changed his mind, one reason to give a sanction of some particular size is nullified. When a defendant has abandoned an attempt, a judge cannot say, in favor of his decision to give the defendant a year in prison, that anticipation of any lower sanction would not have prompted the defendant to recognize sufficient reason to refrain. Since the defendant recognized sufficient reason to refrain without anticipation of sanction, such a claim would be untrue. Other reasons to sanction remain, however--for example, the defendant is deserving of sanction for having wrongfully tried to commit a crime, deterrence goals will be furthered by sanctioning, the judge needs to express solidarity with those targeted by the defendant --and so the fact of abandonment mitigates the sentence by silencing a reason in favor of any given sentence without thereby silencing all such reasons.

Why should the sentence be such as to provide sufficient reason to have refrained from the crime? One rationale for this is rooted in deterrence. The mechanism of deterrence is engagement with the defendant's mechanisms for directing his own conduct; conditions are arranged so the defendant will direct himself away from crime. On the not unreasonable assumption, common in economics, that the mechanisms through which people direct their behavior are guided by their conceptions of their reasons for action, deterrence then requires sanctions harsh enough to provide people with sufficient reason, by their own lights, to refrain. But this is not the only possible rationale. Those who hold that the root of criminal culpability is misuse of the distinctive human capacities for recognizing and responding to reasons (75) will see a different reason to avoid a sanction so low that the defendant would have recognized sufficient reason to commit the crime even if he had anticipated the sanction. Such a sanction would fail to place the defendant in anything like the place of the law-abiding citizen, who would recognize sufficient reason to refrain from crime even without anticipation of sanction. So there are multiple perspectives from which we might justify issuing a sanction large enough that anticipation of it would have prompted the defendant to recognize sufficient reason to refrain from the crime. There are therefore multiple perspectives under which there is good reason to mitigate a sentence because one abandoned an attempt.

Notice that the argument just offered for treating abandonment as a mitigating factor in the sentencing of attempt appeals, implicitly, to the fact that the reasons for sanctioning an attempt are all of them reasons for sanctioning completion (a claim that follows from the Transfer Principle). After all, while remorse after the commission of a crime might be a reason to give a lesser sentence, it is not a mitigating factor thanks to the fact that the defendant would have prospectively recognized sufficient reason to refrain even had he anticipated the lower sanction. For all we know, the remorseful defendant was prospectively aware of the sanction and did not take it to provide him with sufficient reason to refrain; not until after completion did he realize that he shouldn't have committed the crime. Why not say the same thing about the abandoned attempt? After all, abandonment happens after the defendant's crime, namely the attempt, has already taken place. The answer is that abandonment tells us something about the appropriate sanction for the completed crime the defendant attempted. The completed crime would have deserved mitigation since the defendant recognized sufficient reason to refrain from it without considering the typical sanction for the crime. Furthermore, since the reasons to punish attempt derive from the reasons for punishing completion, abandonment mitigates the attempt. It does so for distinctly different reasons from those that would support mitigating in light of remorse.

This point can be put in another way by responding to an objection. It was acknowledged earlier that there can be reasons for sanctioning completion that are not reasons for sanctioning attempt. For instance, we might sanction completion as a way of expressing solidarity with an injured victim. This would not be a reason to sanction attempts of that crime that fall short of injuring anyone. Here we have our objection: how do we know that the reason for sanctioning completion, which is cancelled by the fact of abandonment, is not of this kind? How do we know, that is, that the silenced reason is also a reason to sanction attempt? The answer ultimately comes from the Transfer Principle. To see the answer, first consider the relevance to attempt of the fact that there are victims of the completed crime. If we ask why we criminalize murder, for instance, the harm to murder victims is a central part of the answer. But as I indicated in the discussion of the Transfer Principle in Part I, if we ask why we criminalize attempted murder, the harm to murder victims, a harm not realized in the attempt, is still a central part of the answer. That observation, in fact, is central to appreciating the role of the Transfer Principle in the law of attempt. So while it is true that the expression of solidarity with victims is not a reason to sanction attempts that have no victims, it is also the case that the fact that the completed crime has victims does provide reason to sanction attempt; the reason just is not the expression of solidarity with the victims, but something else. Similarly, part of the reason to criminalize completed crimes is that they spring in part from a failure to recognize sufficient reason to refrain from the crime. And part of the reason to criminalize attempts is that completions involve that failure. Therefore, if this reason to sanction completion is silenced, as I've suggested it is when there is abandonment, then that reason for sanctioning attempt is similarly silenced.

The further and final point worth emphasizing in this section is that we also now have at hand an argument against granting an affirmative defense of abandonment. As indicated earlier, to grant an affirmative defense in the face of a particular condition's being met--such as that the defendant abandoned-- is appropriate only if that condition undermines the rationale for assigning criminal liability. An affirmative defense might also be appropriate if the relevant condition cancels all positive reasons to sanction. But an affirmative defense is the wrong tool if the condition in question provides one reason against sanction, but potentially leaves in place many others. Such is the case with abandonment. It cancels a reason for sanctioning--that is, failure to recognize sufficient reason to refrain--but does not cancel all such reasons. Hence it should be treated as a mitigating factor only; there should be no affirmative defense of abandonment.

D. The Motive for Abandoning

The rationale for mitigation on the basis of abandonment supplied here explains why the motive for abandonment matters. In brief, the reason for this is that when the defendant abandons from some objectionable motive, then the argument for abandonment-based mitigation fails to go through. To see this, we need to consider each of the various types of objectionable motive for abandonment in turn.

The Model Penal Code offers an account of the various motives for abandoning that undermine abandonment's mitigating force. Under the Model Penal Code, the abandonment--what the code chooses to call the "renunciation of criminal purpose"--must be both "voluntary" and "complete" to permit mitigation. But the Code defines these terms in such a way as to identify certain motives for abandonment that undermine abandonment's mitigating force. The relevant section of the Code reads:
   [R]enunciation of criminal purpose is not voluntary if it is
   motivated, in whole or in part, by circumstances, not present or
   apparent at the inception of the actor's course of conduct, that
   increase the probability of detection or apprehension or that make
   more difficult the accomplishment of the criminal purpose.
   Renunciation is not complete if it is motivated by a decision to
   postpone the criminal conduct until a more advantageous time or to
   transfer the criminal effort to another but similar objective or
   victim. (76)


So the Code identifies roughly four kinds of motives for abandonment that undermine mitigation. There is no mitigation if the defendant abandons because (a) there is a better chance he will get caught than he expected; (b) completion is harder than he expected; (c) there will be a better time or place for the crime; or (d) there's a better victim for the crime.

Consider, first, defendants who abandon for the reasons described under (a). The bank robbery, for instance, is abandoned after the defendant walks into the bank, armed and ready to hold up the teller, but notices that a security camera has been installed since he cased the bank. In cases of this sort, the abandonment is predicated upon completion being punished in a way that is typical. The reason that the new security camera provides the defendant with a reason to walk away is that the defendant expects that completion would result in a certain punishment that he has a strong desire to avoid. For all we know, were he to anticipate a smaller than typical punishment, then the added risk of being caught, given the unanticipated camera, would not outweigh the possibility of filling his sack with money. Thus, by abandoning, he has not shown, as the argument for abandonment-based mitigation requires, that he would recognize sufficient reason not to complete the crime even given a lower-than-typical sanction for completion. For all we know, a lower-than-typical sanction would not, given his motives for abandoning, provide him with sufficient reason to refrain and so the argument for abandonment-based mitigation in his case loses its force.

Now consider cases in which the motive is of the sort described under (b), in which completion is more difficult than expected. The bank robbery, for instance, is abandoned at the same point as in our previous example (after the defendant has walked into the bank, armed and intent on robbing it). But in this case, the defendant abandons because he notices that the vault doors are closed, where they were open when he cased the bank, and so the robbery would require him to persuade a bank employee to open the doors for him. There is no reason to believe that the defendant would have recognized sufficient reason to refrain from completing the robbery had he anticipated a smaller than typical sanction. The reason is that anytime anyone undertakes any complicated task, such a task is thought to be worthwhile only if the rewards outweigh the costs that must be borne in order to earn them. For all we know, this defendant included the typical sanction (corrected for the probability that he would have to suffer it) in his calculations before he walked into the bank. The added work of having to open the vault doors tipped the scales against the robbery. But were a cost of the robbery lowered--were a lower-than-typical sanction for completion promised--then it is quite possible that the added work to open the vault doors would be worth undertaking. As in the previous hypothetical, for all we know, a lower than typical sanction would persuade the defendant that he did not, after all, have sufficient reason to abandon. Like before, then, the argument on offer in this Part for abandonment-based mitigation fails when a defendant abandons for the reasons described under (b).

Similar considerations apply when the motives to abandon are like those in (c), in which the defendant realizes that there will be a better time or place to complete the crime, and (d), in which the defendant realizes that there will later be a better victim. Consider someone who abandons the bank robbery when he realizes that a large daily deposit has been delayed and that it will therefore be worth a lot of money to him to rob the bank later. Such a person decides that the risk in this instance is not worth the reward, but that the risk will be worth the reward at a later time. But if robbing the bank now promised a smaller than typical sanction, then for all we know, the risk involved in robbing the bank now would be worth the reward to be expected from robbing it now; after all, less would be risked if the expected sanction for robbing the bank now were lower than typical, and so less would be gained by waiting to rob the bank later. Again, the promise of a lower than typical sanction, given the motive for abandonment, might actually prompt the defendant not to recognize sufficient reason to abandon. Similarly, the defendant who abandons his attempt to rob Bank X because he decides he will be better off robbing Bank Y instead (a case involving a motive of type (d)) sees attractions in robbing Y that outweigh the costs associated with the robbery, including the anticipated sanction (corrected for the probability of being apprehended). But if the robbery of X were to promise a lower than typical sanction, then there might not be sufficient reason to switch targets.

In all these hypothetical cases, the motive for abandonment shows a sensitivity on the defendant's part to the typical sanction. The defendant is weighing pros and cons and deciding to abandon given an assumption on his part that there's a chance he'll suffer the typical sanction should he complete the crime. Thus, when we have these motives for abandonment, it is also true that had the defendant known before he committed the crime that he would suffer a certain smaller than typical sanction for committing it, then he might have found sufficient reason not to abandon his attempt. We therefore have no reason to think that anticipation of a smaller than typical sanction would have been sufficient for awareness of sufficient reason to refrain. As a result, when the defendant has abandoned because of the motives the Model Penal Code identifies, the reason for giving a particular sanction rather than a lower one still applies; it is not silenced by the fact of abandonment. So the argument for abandonment-based mitigation does not go through.

Notice that Arin Ahmed's reasons for abandoning are not of the sort that are sensitive to the expected sanction for the completed crime. That sanction--if it is even possible to imagine what kind of sanction there could be for such behavior, perhaps a penalty issued to one's surviving family members--plays no role in her reasoning; it is not something to be outweighed by other considerations but is simply trumped by the reasons that she had for abandoning. Hence, even if the sanction were smaller, she still would have abandoned her attempt. What follows is that in her case, the argument for abandonment-based mitigation goes through, and so her abandonment is a legitimate mitigating factor.

Could there be other motives for abandonment that undermine the case for abandonment-based mitigation, motives that do not fall into any of the four categories the Model Penal Code identifies? Yes, there could. Consider again the case of People v. Taylor, (77) mentioned at the opening of this Article, in which the defendant's intended rape victim talked him into believing that she would have consensual sex with him, and thus convinced him to stop trying to force her to have sex with him, before locking him out of her apartment. In Taylor, the court rejected the possibility of an abandonment defense under a statute derived from the Model Penal Code. The court did this on the ground that the defendant's renunciation was not "voluntary and complete." However, as noted at the opening of this Article, it is far from clear why it was not, under the Model Penal Code's official definitions of those terms. The best case for thinking that it was not comes from construing the defendant's motives as of type (c)--to construe him, that is, as having merely decided to postpone the rape until later, perhaps after the two returned from the liquor store. But it is hard to see why he would have stopped his attack if this were his motive. After all, if he were intent on rape, he could have completed it despite the victim's efforts to persuade him that he could later have consensual sex with her. Rather, it seems that Taylor forced his way into the apartment with a preference for consensual over non-consensual sex, but intent on having sex with the victim regardless. When he became convinced that consensual sex was a possibility, he pursued it, perhaps anticipating that, should it stop seeming possible, he would return to his pursuit of non-consensual sex. However, even construed in this way, it is not unreasonable to think of Taylor as having changed his mind. His intention to have non-consensual sex was predicated on an assumption: consensual sex was not possible. When he came to believe this assumption was false, he changed his mind and abandoned his plan to have non-consensual sex with the victim. This isn't to say that Taylor ought to enjoy abandonment-based mitigation. He ought not to. But why not? The Model Penal Code does not provide us with a tool for answering; only by distorting the facts are we able to construe Taylor's motive for abandonment as one of the four sorts that undermine abandonment's mitigating force under the Code.

The reason that Taylor's sentence for attempted rape should not be mitigated is because, for all we know, Taylor's preference for consensual over nonconsensual sex was at least in part derived from the fact that non-consensual sex brings with it a certain punishment, the typical punishment for rape. So, if we ask whether someone who abandoned rape for Taylor's reasons would have done so even if the penalty for rape were lower than typical, we find that the answer might very well be "no." After all, had the penalty been lower than typical, then Taylor may have thought that the prospect of consensual sex, bringing with it the risk that he would not have sex with the victim at all, was not worth pursuing. He would abandon only if he thinks that consensual sex outweighs non-consensual sex, a calculation quite possibly made by considering, among other things, the typical penalty for non-consensual sex.

In short, the argument offered here helps us to identify the crucial question that must be answered in deciding whether to grant mitigation on the basis of abandonment: does the fact that the defendant abandoned his attempt show that the defendant would have been dissuaded from completing the crime even if a lower than typical sanction were given for completion? The answer is no when the defendant abandoned for any of the four types of reasons identified by the Model Penal Code. But the answer is no also when the defendant abandoned for reasons like Taylor's, even though those reasons do not fall into any of the Model Penal Code's four categories. Legitimate abandonment-based mitigation is hard to come by, even harder than under the Model Penal Code, since there are motives for abandonment that undermine its mitigating force but that are not identified as such by the Code.

E. Taking Stock

This Part began by identifying an implication of the fact that attempts are properly criminalized thanks to the fact that completions are: the reasons for sanctioning an attempt derive from reasons for sanctioning the corresponding completed crime. This allowed us to identify a class of factors that mitigate sentence for attempt--those that silence a reason for issuing a particular sanction, rather than a lower one, to the corresponding completed crime. By silencing a reason for issuing a high sanction for completion, we thereby necessarily silence a reason for issuing a high sanction for attempt, given the Transfer Principle. In general, the fact that a defendant prospectively recognized sufficient reason to refrain from the crime, without considering the typical sanction for that crime, silences a reason to issue a typical sanction rather than a lower one. This reasoning supports mitigating sentence for the attempt, even though abandonment occurs after the attempt, thanks to the special relationship between the reasons for sanctioning attempt and the reasons for sanctioning completion.

CONCLUSION

This Article offers a theoretical framework for thinking about criminal attempts and draws doctrinal implications from that framework. The theoretical framework consists, in essence, of three components: (1) an account of the grounds for the criminalization of attempts, labeled the Transfer Principle, according to which attempts are implicitly criminalized when we criminalize completed crimes; (2) an account of a wider range of intention-based commitments than has heretofore been recognized; and (3) an account (drawing on (2)), labeled the Guiding Commitment View, of the necessary and sufficient conditions for being a criminal attempt of the sort that is implicitly criminalized when we criminalize completed crimes. To attempt a crime is to be committed by one's intention to each of the components of success and to be guided by that intention.

As we have seen, this theoretical framework allows principled resolution of three seemingly intractable problems that arise in the adjudication of attempt. Three particularly important doctrinal recommendations arise from this resolution: (1) a solicitation rises to the level of a criminal attempt only if the defendant asked another to realize a result element of the completed crime, and not if he asked another to realize an act element. (2) If the defendant believed or intended that the circumstantial elements of the completed crime were in place, then they do not need to be shown to have been in place for conviction for attempt; if, however, the defendant was aware only of the possibility that the circumstantial elements were in place, then the prosecution must show them to have been present to establish the prima facie case for the attempt. Finally, (3) abandonment of an attempt for reasons that show the defendant to have recognized sufficient reason to refrain from the crime without consideration of the prospect of sanction ought to mitigate sentence for attempt and ought not to constitute an affirmative defense. If adopted, all three of these recommendations would bring our practices of adjudicating criminal attempts in line with the principles that animate their criminalization in the first place.

The philosopher Peter Strawson, writing about free will, insisted that in thinking about that topic, we should remind ourselves of some "commonplaces:
   We should think of the many different kinds of relationship which
   we can have with other people--as sharers of a common interest; as
   members of the same family; as colleagues; as friends; as lovers;
   as chance parties to an enormous range of transactions and
   encounters. Then we should think, in each of these connections in
   turn, and in others, of the kind of importance we attach to the
   attitudes and intentions towards us of those who stand in these
   relationships to us, and of the lands of reactive attitudes and
   feelings to which we ourselves are prone....

   The object of these commonplaces is to try to keep before our minds
   something it is easy to forget when we are engaged in philosophy,
   especially in our cool, contemporary style, viz. what it is
   actually like to be involved in ordinary inter-personal
   relationships, ranging from the most intimate to the most casual.
   (78)


As Strawson saw it, the necessary conditions of moral responsibility are those that we find implicit in indispensable social practices of interaction and engagement with others. He urged us, in thinking about what human beings must be like such that we can be held morally responsible for our behavior and hold others responsible, to focus on the varied and complex facts about others and ourselves to which we respond as part of social life, and to which certain responses and not others are particularly appropriate. It is because of its role there that, for instance, intention is so important to responsibility. It is one of the things to which we respond with, among other things, resentment and gratitude; it is one of the things to which some responses, including but not limited to moral emotional responses, and not others, are appropriate.

It is not just this that "our cool, contemporary style" can lead us to forget. It can also lead us to forget the degree to which the assignment of criminal responsibility ought to be, even if it is too rarely, itself an entrenched and integral part of the web of social interactions to which we are necessarily subject thanks to living together in a state. We need an account of what is and should be involved in the assignment of criminal responsibility that demonstrates and exhibits this entrenchment. We must recover the sense in which the assignment of criminal responsibility is an essential part of participation in the many and varied relationships we have with each other as citizens.

The study of criminal responsibility for attempt is not special in this regard. But it is one place in which the theorist is likely to despair, as Jerome Hall did, (79) of the possibility of providing an account of what we are, or should be doing, that bears deep links to the simple interactions of everyday life. We are prone to conceive of the activity as nothing more, for instance, than the post hoc rationalization of the zealous desire to intervene earlier and earlier in the lives of those who, for independent reasons if for any at all, we have classified as inhabiting the wrong side of the law. But this is just pessimism. The law of attempt is the simple interaction between father and daughter writ large. It bears more than an analogical relation to the prohibition of that form of trying that we prohibit implicitly when we prohibit conduct. In fact, it is that prohibition. Or, at least, so it has been argued here.

(1.) The material in this Article developed out of several previous publications, some of which were written as replies to critics of earlier expressions of my views about attempts. Although there are differences between the views I present here and the views I presented in earlier publications, there are also many similarities. This Article consolidates the disparately expressed changes in my position and emphasizes the position's doctrinal implications. See generally Gideon Yaffe, Attempts: In the Philosophy of Action and the Criminal Law (2010); Gideon Yaffe, Attempts, in PHILOSOPHY OF LAW (Joel Feinberg et al. eds., 2013); Gideon Yaffe, Attempt, Risk-Creation, and Change of Mind: Reflections on Herzog, 9 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 779 (2012); Gideon Yaffe, The Legal Importance of Trying: Reply to Enoch, Dahan-Katz, and Berman, 6 JERUSALEM Rev. Legal Stud. 51 (2012); Gideon Yaffe, More Attempts: A Reply to Duff, Husak, Mele and Walen, 6 Crim. L. & PHIL. 429 (2012); Gideon Yaffe, Reply to Jan Broersen, Thomas Nadelhoffer & Steven Sverdlik, 3 JURIS. 489 (20x2); Gideon Yaffe, Trying, Acting and Attempted Crimes, 28 Law & Phil. 109 (2009); Gideon Yaffe, Trying, Intending and Attempted Crimes, 32 PHIL. TOPICS 505 (2006); Gideon Yaffe, Trying to Defend Attempts: Replies to Bratman, Brink, Alexander, and Moore, 19 Legal Theory 178 (20x3); Gideon Yaffe, Trying to Kill the Dead: De Re and De Dicto Intention in Attempted Crimes, in Philosophical Foundations of Law & Language 192-215 (Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames eds., 2011).

(2.) Jerome Hall, Criminal Attempt--A Study of Foundations of Criminal Liability, 49 Yale L.J. 789, 789 (1940).

(3.) While many codes have specific sections criminalizing attempts, it is common for them to say no more than that it is a crime to attempt a crime--without specifying what conditions need to be met for a person's behavior to constitute an attempt. See, e.g., CAL. Penal Code [section] 664 (West 2012); Mass. Gen. Laws ch. 24, [section] 6 (2011); Mich. Compiled Laws [section] 750.92 (2004); Tenn. Code Ann. [section] 59-12-101 (2011).

(4.) See, e.g., Gregg v. United States, 113 F.2d 687, 690 (8th Cir. 1940) (requiring "direct movement towards" the completion of the crime); People v. Collins, 234 N.Y. 355 (1922) (requiring "direct movement towards" completion and an act that "tends but fails" to lead to completion of the crime).

(5.) People v. Decker, 157 P.3d 1017,1019 (Cal. 2007).

(6.) Id.

(7.) Cal. Penal Code [section] 653f(b) (West 2012).

(8.) Decker, 157 P.3d at 1022.

(9.) United States v. Crow, 164 F.3d 229 (5th Cir. 1999).

(10.) Id. at 232.

(11.) Id. at 234.

(12.) Id.

(13.) Id. at 234-35.

(14.) Impressed by this point, some courts have embraced the result the Crow court endeavored to avoid, acquitting similarly situated defendants of attempt. On facts very similar to those in

Crow, for instance, the court in Aplin v. State, 889 N.E.2d 882, 884 (Ind. Ct. App. 2008), overruled by King v. State, 921 N.E.2d 1288 (Ind. 2010), acquitted the defendant on the ground that his conduct "did not constitute the offense of attempted Sexual Misconduct with a Minor, because Detective Claasen [who was posing as a fifteen-year-old girl in his Internet conversations with the defendant] is an adult." King v. State, 921 N.E.2d 1288 (Ind. 2010), however, overruled this decision and brought Indiana law in line with the approach adopted by the court in Crow.

(15.) People v. Taylor, 598 N.E.2d 693, 695 (N.Y. 1992).

(16.) Id.

(17.) Id.

(18.) Id. at 700.

(19.) Id. (citing N.Y. Penal Law [section] 40.10(5) (Consol. 2014)). In general, courts have interpreted the Model Penal Code's conception of "voluntary and complete" renunciation very narrowly. Consider United States v. Bailey, 834 F.2d 218, 226-27 (1st Cir. 1987). The defendant offered a juror money in exchange for a vote to acquit. A day later, the offer was declined. There was evidence that before the offer was declined, but after it was issued, the defendant regretted having made the offer and had lost sleep over her decision to do so. The trial court refused to instruct the jury on the affirmative defense of abandonment, a defense modeled on the Model Penal Code's, and the appellate court upheld this decision on the grounds that the evidence of "complete" renunciation was insufficient. But since the Model Penal Code does not require that the defendant take any positive steps toward preventing the completion of the crime to abandon it, it is far from clear why a reasonable jury could not have found that Bailey abandoned.

(20.) Too many thinkers have taken positions on attempt to allow for anything close to an exhaustive classification here of each as subjectivist or objectivist. The distinction is made in George Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law 166-97 (2000). Fletcher defends a form of objectivism, as does R. A. Duff, CRIMINAL Attempts (1996). Objectivist leanings, at least, can be detected in Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Common Law 69-70 (1881); Francis B. Sayre, Criminal Attempts, 41 Harv. L. Rev. 821 (1928); and Peter Westen, Impossibility Attempts: A Speculative Thesis, 5 Ohio St. J. Crim. L. 523 (2008). Subjectivism's proponents include Larry Alexander & Kimberly K. Ferzan, Crime and Culpability: A Theory of Criminal Law (2009); Andrew Ashworth, Criminal Attempts and the Role of Resulting Harm Under the Code, and in the Common Law, 19 RUTGERS LJ. 725 (1988); Stephen J. Morse, Reason, Results, and Criminal Responsibility, 2004 U. ILL. L. Rev. 363; and J.C. Smith, Two Problems in Criminal Attempts, 70 Harv. L. Rev. 422 (1957).

(21.) Of course, some statutes explicitly prohibit attempt as well as completion. E.g., D.C. Code Ann. [section] 22-303 (2006) (providing that "[w]hoever maliciously injures or breaks or destroys, or attempts to injure or break or destroy ... any public or private property" shall be punished) (emphasis added). But this does not undermine the point. In such cases, there are two sources of the criminalization of the attempt: the statute prohibiting the attempt and the statute prohibiting the completion.

(22.) In his classic 1957 article, J.C. Smith claims that what I am calling the wide sense of trying is the sense of relevance to the criminal law of attempts. See Smith, supra note 20. For the reasons explained below, Smith is mistaken.

(23.) See, e.g., G.E.M. Anscombe, Intention (1957); Michael E. Bratman, Faces of Intention: Selected Essays on Intention and Agency (1999) [hereinafter Bratman, Faces]; Michael E. Bratman, Intention, Plans, and Practical Reasoning (1987) [hereinafter Bratman, Intention] ; Michael E. Bratman, Structures of Agency (2007) [hereinafter Bratman, Structures] ; John Broome, Rationality Through Reasoning (2013); Donald Davidson, Intending, in Essays on Actions and Events 83 (2001); Gilbert Harman, Change in View: Principles of Reasoning (1986); Alfred Mele, Springs of Action: Understanding Intentional Behavior (1992); Kieran Setiya, Reasons without Rationalism (2007); Donald Davidson, Actions, Reasons and Causes, 60 J. Phil. 685 (1963); Wayne A. Davis, A Causal Theory of Intending, 21 Am. Phil. Q. 43 (1984); H. Paul Grice, In-

tention and Uncertainty, 57 Proc. British Acad. 263 (1971); Gilbert Harman, Practical Reasoning, 29 Rev. Metaphysics 431 (1976).

(24.) Legal scholarship is replete with examples of studies of the relationship between ordinary notions and their corresponding legal manifestations. See, e.g., Ian Ayres & Gregory Klaas, Insincere Promises: The Law of Misrepresented Intent (2005); Michael S. Moore, Causation and Responsibility: An Essay in Law, Morals, and Metaphysics (2009); Peter Westen, The Logic of Consent (2004).

(25.) The example is G.E.M. Anscombe's. See ANSCOMBE, supra note 23, at 56.

(26.) A number of legal theorists have used Bratman's work to their advantage. See, e.g., Scott J. Shapiro, Legality (2011); Kimberly Kessler Ferzan, Beyond Intention, 29 Cardozo L. Rev. 1147 (2007); Gideon Yaffe, Conditional Intent and Mens Rea, 10 LEGAL THEORY 273 (2004).

(27.) Bratman, Faces, supra note 23; Bratman, Intention, supra note 23; Bratman, Structures, supra note 23.

(28.) For views of the nature of responsibility that are supportive of this point, see, for instance, John Martin Fischer & Mark Ravizza, Responsibility and Control: A Theory of

Moral Responsibility (1998); Susan Wolf, Freedom Within Reason (1990); and T.M. Scanlon, The Significance of Choice, in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 151 (1986).

(29.) An exception, arguably, is Hector Neri-Castaneda, whose work deserves to receive much more attention from philosophers of action. For a start, see his article Intentions and the Structure of Intending, 68 J. Phil. 453 (1971).

(30.) Bratman, Intention, supra note 23, at 31.

(31.) Holmes, supra note 20, at 68-69.

(32.) People v. Superior Court, 157 P.3d 1017, 1019 (Cal. 2007). More precisely, the court reached the conclusion that a reasonable jury could so find and so held that a solicitation like Decker's could be an attempt under California law. Id. at 1022.

(33.) 111 Cal. Rptr. 544 (Ct. App. 1973).

(34.) People v. Otto, 629 P.2d 646 (Idaho 1981); Commonwealth v. Hamel, 752 N.E.2d 808 (Mass. App. Ct. 2001); Johnson v. Sherriffi 532 P.2d 1037 (Nev. 1975); State v. Disanto, 688 N.W.2d 201 (S.D. 2004).

(35.) Howell v. State, 278 S.E.2d 43 (Ga. Ct. App. 1981); State v. Leggio, 781 N.W.2d 100 (Iowa Ct. App. 2010); People v. Sabo, 687 N.Y.S.2d 513 (Sup. Ct. 1998); State v. Group, 781 N.E.2d 980 (Ohio 2002).

(36.) In State v. Arave, 268 P.3d 163 (Utah 2011), such a solicitation was taken to be insufficient for attempt, while in Ishee v. State, 799 So. 2d 70 (Miss. 2001), an attempt conviction on similar facts was upheld.

(37.) See People v. Murray, 14 Cal. 159 (1859) (holding that the evidence did not sustain a conviction for attempt).

(38.) See State v. Bailer, 26 W. Va. 90 (1885) (holding that the request did not amount to an attempt despite the fact that money was given for the bribe).

(39.) In State v. Taylor, 84 P. 82 (Or. 1906), soliciting someone to burn down a barn was attempted arson, while in State v. Donovan, 90 A. 220 (Del. 1914), soliciting someone to burn down a warehouse was not.

(40.) See State v. Sunzar, 751 A.2d 627 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1999) (ruling that it was an attempt to ask someone to move hazardous waste).

(41.) Cases of this sort have less to do with conspiracy, since that crime requires all parties to be planning to commit a crime. In cases like Decker's, there is no meeting of the minds. While Holston said that he agreed to kill Decker's sister, he did not actually agree to any such thing. See People v. Superior Court, 157 P.3d 1017 (Cal. 2007).

(42.) Section 2.06(3) (a) (i) If the Model Penal Code makes solicitation itself sufficient for accomplice liability, and the commentary makes clear that this is so even if the solicitation had no actual influence on the principal's performance of the crime. See Model Penal Code [section] 2.06 cmt. 6(c) (Official Draft 1962). However, sometimes courts have required not just a showing of solicitation, but also a showing to the effect that the principal was motivated to act by the solicitation. See, e.g., Workman v. State, 21 N.E.2d 712, 714 (Ind. 1939) ("It is only necessary that the appellant counseled and advised the commission of the crime, and that the counsel and advice influenced the perpetration of the crime.").

(43.) Sometimes whether this has occurred is less than clear. For instance, in People v. Berger, 280 P.2d 136 (Cal. Ct. App. 1955), the defendant, a doctor, was asked by a pregnant investigator for the district attorney's office to help her procure an illegal abortion. The defendant asked Inez Brown to do the procedure. Brown came to the investigator's home bearing various medical tools and began to prepare for the procedure, which she clearly intended to perform. Brown was then arrested and Berger was charged as Brown's accomplice. Here the hard question is whether Brown did enough to have attempted the abortion; the court said she did. Berger's conviction for attempt was then upheld simply by applying standard rules of accomplice liability under which the kind of solicitation that Berger made of Brown is enough to find that Berger was Brown's accomplice.

(44.) The Model Penal Code would not call these cases of "accomplice" liability but would instead consider them to be cases in which the defendant is "legally accountable for the conduct of another," reserving the term "accomplice" for cases in which the offense is actually committed by the party solicited. But the terms are not important. What matters is this: to motivate another to engage in conduct sufficient for the act element of the crime can be equivalent, for legal purposes, to engaging in such conduct oneself. See Model Penal Code [section] 2.06(2)(a) (Official Draft 1962). There are other differences between those who are "legally accountable for the conduct of another" and those who are "accomplices." Most important, the mens rea requirements for the former are the same as those required for the completed crime, while accomplices need only satisfy lesser mens rea requirements.

(45.) The case also defies resolution in another way. In some two-party cases, the defendant's solicitation is a means toward completion of the crime by the defendant himself. The defendant who asks another to deliver a threatening letter to a witness is trying to threaten a witness himself. The solicitation is part of the defendant's own criminal attempt. See, e.g., People v. Coleman, 86 N.W.2d 281 (Mich. 1957). However, here Decker was asking Holston to kill Decker's sister, thus obviating the need for Decker to do it himself.

(46.) The Model Penal Code has a provision designed to solve a different problem but which appears at first glance to allow us to deal with cases that defy resolution through familiar accomplice liability principles: "A person who engages in conduct designed to aid another to commit a crime that would establish his complicity ... if the crime were committed by such other person, is guilty of an attempt to commit the crime, although the crime is not committed or attempted by such other person." MODEL PENAL CODE [section] 5.01(3) (Official Draft 1962). Although the defendant would be complicit in the solicited party's crime were the solicited party to do as asked, the defendant, in a hard solicitation-as-attempt case like Decker, does not "engage in conduct designed to aid" the solicited party. Solicitations aren't ordinarily designed to help others do as asked. Note the difference between this language and the language defining the mens rea required for accomplice liability as having a "purpose of promoting or facilitating" the commission of the offense. Id. [section] 2.06(3)(a) (emphasis added). In the most difficult cases, the defendant has the mens rea needed to be an accomplice but not the mens rea needed to fall under Section 5.01(3). Also, if we interpret Section 5.01(3) more broadly than this reading suggests, then it follows that all solicitations are attempts. If that's what the Model Penal Code says, then one starts to wonder what point there is in having crimes of solicitation at all, given that they always warrant lesser sentences than attempts.

(47.) Ordinarily, theorists give up on the distinction among act, result, and circumstantial elements of crimes. But they should not. The key is to recognize that the distinction between them is in the burden each element places on the prosecutor, rather than in the nature of the events themselves that constitute the crime. The prosecution bears three burdens with respect to act elements. They must show that the event occurred, that the defendant caused it, and that the defendant was active with respect to it. The prosecution bears only the first two burdens when the element is a result and only the first when it is a circumstance.

(48.) Cal. Penal Code [section] 187(a) (West 2014).

(49.) Model Penal Code [section] 220.3(i)(c) (Official Draft 1962).

(50.) Could the deception or threat be construed as a result element of this crime? If A causes B to threaten C in such a way as to cause C pecuniary loss, is A guilty under this statute? Standard principles of causation would preclude guilt in such a case because B's threat would amount to voluntary intervention and so A would not in that case have caused C's pecuniary loss. Therefore, deception or threat must be an act element of the crime.

(51.) Model Penal Code [section] 210.1(1) (Official Draft 1962).

(52.) Decker has not attempted to kill; but just as one can murder without killing under the Model Penal Code, one can attempt murder without attempting to kill under it.

53. The Model Penal Code does not provide much by way of a normative defense of this claim, but says only, "It seems clear that causing death purposely, knowingly, and recklessly ... must in the absence of justification or excuse establish criminality." Model Penal Code [section] 210.1 cmt (Official Draft 1962). I quite agree. The important point for our purposes is that it is not so under homicide laws like those in California when they are read literally.

(54.) One might wonder if we could reach the doctrinal result argued for here--namely, that a solicitation of a result crime rises to the level of an attempt but not a solicitation of an act crime--just by appeal to the Transfer Principle and without the Guiding Commitment View. But we cannot. Imagine an alternative to the Guiding Commitment View according to which a person attempts an act provided he has an intention that commits him to causing the result involved in the act; he is trying to kill, for instance, provided he has an intention-based commitment to causing the death, even if he lacks an intention-based commitment to being active with respect to that death. Such a view would have different implications with respect to solicitation-as-attempt cases than the Guiding Commitment View. Therefore, it is essential to the argument here that the Guiding Commitment View, and not other views of the nature of attempt, supports the Transfer Principle.

(55.) 78 N.E. 169 (N.Y. 1906).

(56.) Id. at 169.

(57.) See id. at 170-71 (Chase, J., dissenting).

(58.) See Larry Alexander, Inculpatory and Exculpatory Mistakes and the Fact/Law Distinction: An Essay in Memory of Myke Balyes, 12 Law & Phil. 33 (1993); Kenneth W. Simons, Mistake and Impossibility, Law and Fact, and Culpability: A Speculative Essay, 81J. CRIM. L. & CRIMINOLOGY 447 (1990). One obvious problem is that many obstacles that courts hope to classify as "factual" are legally constituted. The property that Jaffe received had been stolen and then recovered. That recovered property is not properly classified as "stolen" is a legal fact, but such a case would ordinarily be classified as one of factual impossibility. It is difficult to see why.

(59.) Compare United States v. Butters, 267 F. App'x 773 (10th Cir. 2008) (deeming the absence of an actual minor "irrelevant"), and Laughner v. State, 769 N.E.2d 1147 (Ind. Ct. App. 2002) (holding that soliciting sex from an undercover agent whom the defendant thought was a minor was attempt), with Gibbs v. State, 898 N.E.2d 1240 (Ind. Ct. App. 2008), overruled by King v. State, 921 N.E.2d 1288 (Ind. 2010) (holding that a case could not be proved because it did not actually involve a minor), and People v. Thousand, 614 N.W.2d 674 (Mich. Ct. App. 2000), rev'd, 631 N.W.2d 694 (Mich. 2001) (dismissing the charge of attempt because the defendant's "object of ... desire" was actually an adult and not a minor).

(60.) 482 F.2d 171 (3d Cir. 1973).

(61.) Id. at 179.

(62.) Id. at 184.

(63.) Id. at 189-90. One recent case reaches the same kind of conclusion through very different reasoning from that employed in Berrigan. In Moore v. State, 882 A.2d 256 (Md. 2005), the defendant made arrangements with an undercover detective whom he believed to be fourteen years old to meet to have sex. The appellate court noted that the completed crime is strict liability with respect to age, and so can be committed by someone in the absence of an intention to have sex with a minor; even someone who intends to have sex with an adult can be guilty of the completed offense provided that the person he has sex with is actually a minor. The court then analogized strict liability crimes to crimes of negligence, like involuntary manslaughter, that cannot be committed with intent. Id. at 268-69. Someone who intends to kill is guilty of a purposive homicide rather than involuntary manslaughter, and this gives rise to the rule that there is no crime of attempted involuntary manslaughter. This same reasoning applies to any other crime that cannot be completed with intent. Extending this well-known rule, the court concluded that it is not possible to attempt a strict liability crime such as that at issue in the case; as a result, the defendant was acquitted. Id. at 269-70. After all, reasoned the court, completed strict liability crimes do not involve intent any more than crimes of negligence do. The problem with the court's reasoning is that strict liability crimes, unlike involuntary manslaughter and other crimes of negligence, can be committed by someone with the intention that an attempter has; they just don't require such an intention. So even those who think that there are no attempts of crimes like involuntary manslaughter can consistently hold that there are attempts of strict liability crimes. In fact, some courts have taken it to be easier to attempt crimes of strict liability; they have thought that in such cases not even belief that the relevant circumstantial element is in place is required for the attempt. Cf. Commonwealth v. Dunne, 474 N.E.2d 538, 544-45 (Mass. 1985) (upholding conviction for attempted statutory rape in the absence of any evidence of defendant's mens rea with respect to the victim's age).

(64.) The example is singled out, also in a discussion of abandoned attempts, by JOSHUA Dressler, Cases and Materials on Criminal Law 800 (4th ed. 2007).

(65.) Id. (quoting Vered Levy-Barzilai, Prisoners' Dilemmas, Harper's Mag., Sept. 2002, at 17, 21).

(66.) Model Penal Code [section] 5-01(4) (Official Draft 1962). The Model Penal Code provides for abandonment defenses to conspiracy, as well as solicitation. Id. [section][section] 5.02(3), 5.03(6).

(67.) Evan Tsen Lee, Cancelling Crime, 30 CONN. L. Rev. 117,120 n.13 (1997).

(68.) See, e.g., id. at 118.

(69.) See, e.g., United States v. Shelton, 30 F.3d 702, 706-07 (6th Cir. 1994) ("There is no objective evidence corroborating [the defendant's] alleged change of heart; rather, all of Shelton's actions were consistent with the planned commission of the offense."); United States v. Tanks, No. 92-3023,1992 WL 317179, at *6 (6th Cir. Oct. 27, 1992) ("[T]here is not any evidentiary support for ... an instruction [on abandonment] in this case.").

(70.) The so-called "probable desistance" test for the act element of attempt makes the mistake of thinking that whether a defendant's conduct suffices depends on whether he will desist from it. This is to hold that it is possible for two defendants who are duplicates in action, mental state, and circumstances, but not in propensities that are unrealized in action or mental state, to differ in whether they have attempted a crime. That is an indefensible result.

(71.) For a trenchant economic analysis of this argument, see Murat C. Mungan, Abandoned Criminal Attempts: An Economic Analysis (Fla. State Univ. Coll, of Law, Public Law Research Paper No. 652, 2013), http://ssm.com/abstract=234455i [http://perma.cc/NBH5-XW2L]. The argument is mentioned in many other places in the law and economics literature about attempt. See Omri Ben-Shahar, Criminal Attempts, in 1 The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics AND THE Law 546, 547-48 (Peter Newman ed., 1998); Samuel Kramer, An Economic Analysis of Criminal Attempt: Marginal Deterrence and the Optimal Structure of Sanctions, 81 J. Crim L. & CRIMINOLOGY 398, 401 (1990); Richard A. Posner, An Economic Theory of the Criminal Law, 85 Colum. L. Rev. 1193,1217-18 (1985); Steven Shavell, Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent, 85 COLUM. L. Rev. 1232, 1232-33 (1985); Steven Shavell, Deterrence and the Punishment of Attempts, 19 J. Legal Stud. 435 (1990).

(72.) Imagine denying that the motive for abandonment matters. Under such a view, anyone who runs from the police when interrupted before completion of a crime is to be given mitigation or defense on grounds of abandonment. This is to radically shrink attempt liability. Even unflinching believers in deterrence as the sole purpose of criminal sanction, then, must recognize that the motive for abandonment matters. To ignore it would be to undermine, even, the deterrent function of attempt liability, not to mention its retributive and expressive purposes.

(73.) Model Penal Code [section] 3.03 (Official Draft 1962).

(74.) Under the United States Sentencing Guidelines Manual, criminal history aggravates sentence. U.S. Sentencing Guidelines Manual [section] 4A1.1 (2004). This may be equivalent to allowing the absence of criminal history to mitigate.

(75.) See supra Part II.

(76.) Model Penal Code [section] 5.01(4) (Official Draft 1962).

(77.) 598 N.E.2d 693 (N.Y. 1992).

(78.) Peter Strawson, Freedom and Resentment, in Free Will 72, 76-77 (Gary Watson ed., 2003).

(79.) Hall, supra note 2, at 789.

Professor of Law and Professor of Philosophy & Psychology, Yale Law School. So many people have helped with the development of this project over the years that it is absolutely impossible to thank them all. I start by thanking the authors of the many published critical commentaries on my earlier work on attempt. Their work has benefited the present project immensely: Lany Alexander, Mitch Berman, Michael Bratman, David Brink, Jan Broersen, Antony Duff, David Enoch, Leora Dahan-Katz, Doug Husak, Alfred Mele, Michael Moore, Thomas Nadelhoffer, Steven Sverdlik, and Alec Walen. Thanks are also owed to my former colleagues at the University of Southern California, conversations with whom forced me to figure out what I really think, and to re-think that. Thanks in this respect are especially owed to Steve Finlay, Greg Keating, Andrei Marmor, Jacob Ross, Mark Schroeder, Scott Soames, and Gary Watson. And, finally, thanks to my new colleagues at Yale Law School, especially Bruce Ackerman, Tracey Meares, Robert Post, Jed Rubenfeld, and Scott Shapiro, for encouraging me to seek a broader audience for this work than I am naturally wont to do. In addition, invaluable help was provided by Ben Eidelson. To describe his contribution as that of a "research assistant" is to radically understate the case.
COPYRIGHT 2014 Yale University, School of Law
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2014 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Title Annotation:IV. Trying by Asking: Solicitation as Attempt B. Act Crimes, Result Crimes: How Courts Should Decide through Conclusion, p. 124-156
Author:Yaffe, Gideon
Publication:Yale Law Journal
Date:Oct 1, 2014
Words:19323
Previous Article:Criminal attempts.
Next Article:The rise of institutional mortgage lending in early nineteenth-century New Haven.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2020 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters