Printer Friendly

An early reference to perfect numbers? Some notes on Euphorion, 'SH' 417.

[Elias] In Porphyrii Isagogen 8.21 (Paris. gr. 1939 f. 26v, Monac. gr. 399 f. 165 r): [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

[GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

[GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Par. ante corr.: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Monac., Par. post corr. [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] codd., corr. Westerink [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] codd.: corr. Westerink [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] codd., corr. Westerink [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Westerink: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] E. Hussey: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] codd. [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Westerink [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] E. Hussey: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

These perfect numbers are also attested by Euphorion in the Mopsopia, when he says: `...equal to his (their) limbs, with the result that they are called perfect'.

Euphorion SH417 (fr. 36 Van Groningen) deserves to be better known.(2) A curiosity in itself--an apparent poetic reference to number theory--it is also, potentially, one of our earliest references to Euclidean material. On the authority of a late commentator on Aristotle, Euphorion, a mid-third-century B.C. Euboean poet who was also active in Athens and Antioch, is said to have mentioned perfect numbers--i.e, numbers which equal the total of all their factors, including 1 (but obviously excluding the number itself). It is a pity that the context in Euphorion does not survive, and that the line is only preserved, and indeed interpreted, by so late a source. But the wording of the fragment--if Westerink's restoration of its various corruptions (again, a pity) is plausible--would strongly suggest a reference to the notion of perfect number. The fragment has been known since Westerink published it in 1960, and was included both in Van Groningen's edition of Euphorion in 1977 and in Supplementum Hellenisticum (1983). But its implications have still not been discussed, and when David Fowler came to gather the evidence for references to Euclidean material in and after the third century B.C. in The Mathematics of Plato's Academy, his attention, unsurprisingly, was not drawn to it.(3) Euphorion has had a bad press, as a poet of rebarbatively obscure myth and intractable vocabulary; yet he holds some interest, and we may be missing more insights into the intellectual life of the Hellenistic period which the perverse intelligence and baneful wit of the fragments display.

SOURCE

The fragment was discovered by L. G. Westerink and published as `A new fragment of Euphoric', Mnemosyne s.4. 13 (1960), 329-30. Van Groningen (fr. 36) misleadingly implied that it derived from the Aristotle commentator, David, from a fuller text of his discussion of perfect numbers.(4) But it does not come from David; rather, it is from a text that goes under the name of pseudo-Elias (henceforth [Elias]), published by Westerink as Pseudo-Elias (Pseudo-David}: Lectures on Porphyry's Isagoge (Amsterdam, 1967). This is an obscure and undistinguished text, curious in the density of its medical learning. As Westerink's introduction says (pp. xi-xvi), it overlaps with material from other Aristotle commentators, especially Elias and David, to both of whom it is attributed by titles in different manuscripts. Probably the author is identical with neither, though does belong to the same teaching tradition. Westerink gives his termini as the end of the sixth century, on the one hand, and the closure of the university of Constantinople in 726, on the other.

The beginning of the text is lost. What we have(5) begins with a recapitulation of the conventional theme of the reason for the six [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (definitions) of philosophy, and proceeds with a derivative account of even and odd numbers and their various species, even-times-even, odd- even, and even-odd. This jejune account is quite unoriginal, deriving mostly from David and Nicomachus. [Elias] then leads into his discussion of perfect and imperfect numbers (8.7); he compares perfect numbers with perfectly formed humans; [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] or over-perfect numbers (whose factors add up to more than the number itself) with `over-endowed' monsters like the hundred-handed Briareus; and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] or less-than-perfect numbers (whose factors add up to less) with the deficient, like monophthalmic Cyclops. He then defines and exemplifies these three types of number (8.12-15); remarks on the rarity of perfection in numerology as in everything else, for only one such number is to be found among the tens, the hundreds, the thousands, and the ten-thousands; and observes that perfect numbers end in 6 and 8 alternately (8.16-20).(6) Elias now relaxes the turgidly elementary maths: enter Euphorion (8.21). These perfect numbers, [Elias] says (not indicating which), are alluded to in Euphorion's Mopsopia. The lecture ends with a restatement: how reasonable it is, then, and how natural, that there should be six definitions of philosophy.

Unfortunately the line is corrupt. The title of the poem, the Mopsopia--independently attested (frr. 34-6 P.)--is the least of the difficulties; as Westerink says, -[GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]-in the manuscript could easily have arisen from the word [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], frequent in the context in [Elias]. More serious is that [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], is Westerink's restoration. But it seems fairly secure. The first half of the line must explain why some numbers are called `perfect'; [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] supplies the required sense, and it hardly matters that it is not the word [Elias] himself uses.(7) If it is right, Euphorion could be echoing the standard definition of perfect numbers given in Euclid, El. 7 Def. 23: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].(8)

Nearly all [Elias] says about perfect numbers comes from Nicomachus. The latter flourished around A.D. 100; a popularizer, he was more interested in the `mystic rather than the mathematical side of the theory of numbers'.(9) Though `not really a mathematician', he made mathematics as easy and accessible as his overheated and mystagogic style would allow, and [Elias] names him elsewhere as one pre-eminent in [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (19.30). He, like [Elias], exemplifies over-perfect numbers by Briareus, and quotes the Hesiodic hexameter about the Cyclops to illustrate the less-than-perfect variety.(10) When [Elias] compares the pattern of alternate endings in 6 and 8 to that of a sieve, the word would seem to have been suggested by the Eratosthenic [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] which Nicomachus has described in the immediately preceding section (1.13). The one thing Nicomachus does not mention is Euphorion's line. But might an earlier, Or fuller, text or commentary have done so? It is also interesting that the quotation from Hesiod found in this section seems to be the only occasion in the Introductio Arithmetica when Nicomachus turns to poetry. Was there a tradition of exemplifying perfect numbers from poetry, a tradition in which the lines of both Hesiod and Euphorion were originally quoted? Or is the quotation from Euphorion [Elias]'s own independent addition? Whatever his source, he does not look very sure about what use he wants to make of the quotation, which is oddly tacked on at the end, reminiscent of an afterthought, or as if the author was so pleased with a sudden insight into an obscure hexameter that he could not resist writing it down. [Elias] cites numerous other poets, usually passages which have entered the mainstream of Aristotle commentary.(11) But a few citations cannot be paralleled from the other commentators, citations which might have come from lexica, for example, or anthologies.(12) Does Euphorion's line come from a lost commentary or lexicon entry? We do not know. Edward Hussey, observing the density of the medical learning in [Elias], suggests to me by letter that the author perhaps got the line of Euphorion from some medical compilation; indeed, the number six was thought by some to have medical implications.(13) But for the time being at least, the source of the line is a mystery.

EUPHORION'S KNOWLEDGE OF PERFECT NUMBERS

It is far from clear that Euphorion is referring to a text of Euclid himself, rather than that he is paraphrasing a mathematical cliche worded in this way before Euclid laid it down. If one more competent in Greek mathematics than I were to assert that perfect numbers could not have been defined, worded, in this way before Euclid, then we would have a reference to the--or a--text of Euclid himself from the middle of the third century B.C. If, on the other hand, perfect numbers were conceptualized and defined in this way before Euclid, then Euphorion might equally well be referring to a notion he had picked up elsewhere, This is the central question. Had Euphorion read Euclid; or have we here evidence that the idea may have been in more general circulation?

The facts, such as they are, are well-known. [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] first appears in Euclid El. 7 Def. 23: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] At 9.36 Euclid shows the law of their formation.(14) Perfect numbers are next mentioned by Theon of Smyrna pp. 45.9ff. and Nicomachus 1.16, Iamblichus In Nicont 32.20 ff., who add information about hyper- and hypoperfect numbers,(15) It is presumably from Nicomachu that the doctrine becomes a topos in the Aristotle commentators.

The date of Euclid is irremediably obscure; the consensus tends to be that his floruit was around 300 B.C., and he is associated with a school in Alexandria.(16) Euphorion is not known to have had any direct connection with Alexandria,(17) though he certainly knew Alexandrian poetry. It does not seem at all unlikely that he might have known the work of a recent Alexandrian mathematician; but there is another place where he might have picked up the doctrine of perfect numbers, and that is Athens. He almost certainly received training there in philosophy in the middle of the third century B.C., and it is likely that Euclid was educated in Athens too.(18) It is surely at least as likely that Euphorion got his perfect numbers from his education in Athens as that he got them straight from Euclid, A further argument might be derived from the single-word fragment 151 P., cited without context. It contains the single-word [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] It might mean simply `defective', but the word is extraordinarily rare in poetry, and I can parallel it only by [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] in Euangelus, a comic poet of perhaps the third century B.C.(19) The very rarity of the general meaning `defective' could, as Westerink saw, be an argument for assigning it a technical sense in Euphorion, referring to numbers which are `less than perfect', those whose factors add up to less than the number itself. But this notion is absent from the text of Euclid himself. It is first found in Theon of Smyrna and Nicomachus, in their discussions of perfect numbers. Here would be evidence that Euphorion did not know the contents of Euclid as we know them, but had picked up a notion which had gained general mathematical currency in the academies of his day.

PRE-EUCLIDEAN PERFECT NUMBERS?

The Pythagorean perfect triangle, the [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], was a pebble-figure consisting of ten individual pebbles arranged in rows of 1 + 2 + 3 + 4.(20) Later commentators point out the difference between the various applications of the term `perfect number' in antiquity.(21) The Pythagoreans do not seem to have assigned any particular importance to the number 6, though, as Burkert observes, a riddle in an epigram tells us that they did list 28 pupils of Pythagoras, and there were also supposed to have been 28 members of the Academy.(22) The epigram presents the number of the followers of Pythagoras precisely in the form of the total of the factors of 28, yet it is clearly late and need not represent early Pythagorean teaching. It belongs to a group (AP 14.1-4) in which a larger number is represented as a total of smaller numbers; the others are not perfect, but the method is the same, additive, one as the way in which perfect numbers are produced. It is intriguing, but can hardly be used as evidence for the state of number theory in or before the third and fourth centuries B.C.

Could the Pythagoreans be responsible for the notion of perfect number which led to the designation of 6, 28 and the rest as [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] It is a priori very likely that it was around before Euclid. By letter, David Fowler comments that `the suggestion that... perfect numbers were not known much before Euclid... would be seen as startlingly revolutionary by most, perhaps all people working on Greek mathematics, though... the evidential basis for it is very tenuous'. One way in which the notion could have been discovered is proposed by Taisbak.(23) This hypothesis depends on addition and duplication, and presupposes the use of Egyptian-style multiplication tables by the Greeks, but, like Euclid's rule for finding them, it depends essentially on the fact that a perfect number is produced by multiplying the total number achieved by adding together the terms in the series of duplications 1, 2, 4, 8, and soon, whenever this total number is itself prime, by the last term in the series. Taisbak concludes that a Pythagorean could be a candidate for discovery of this idea, and Becker had already laid the notion at the same door. In an article that is often held to have settled the matter once and for all, he argued that Euclid 7.21-34 and definitions 7.6-11, which concern odd and even numbers, are a group of early Pythagorean propositions preserved out of reverence for their antiquity, despite their lack of connection with anything else in books 7-9 (and their lack of profundity in comparison with the rest of those books), and whose purpose was originally to lead up to the proposition on perfect numbers.(24) Of the method of producing them, the dyadic process of continuous doubling, he says that `the Egyptian method of calculation should certainly be assumed as its origin'.

Burkert, however, is sceptical. Plato's Academy is the better place to look; Becker's attribution of the notion to the Pythagoreans contains the seeds of its own destruction, because it presupposes the use of algebraic notation which would have been unavailable to those who proceeded by such empirical means as black-and-white counters; the concepts conveyed by the algebraic notation simply could not have been developed by those to whom such notation was unknown.(25) Burkert, however, may have been unduly impressed by the more technical sections of Becker's article. It is indeed hard to conceive that the Pythagoreans would have had the means to express some of the ideas in Becker's article (take the formulations on p. 95). Neither, for that matter, would the Platonic Academy. But neither would they need to. Becker deliberately and explicitly constructed his proofs in such a way that they could have been carried out with counters.(26)

The real problem is the identity of the Pythagoreans, even the possibility of mapping out their intellectual interests to the extent of being able to assert or to deny that they were the ones who first conceptualized perfect numbers But the notion is surely not all that difficult, and, at least if perfect numbers are calculated by Euclid's method, then it must follow the notion of prime numbers. The term [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] seems first to occur in an extant text in Aristotle.(27) The notion might go back at least to the early Pythagorean Philolaus, who flourished in the second half of the fifth century, but the testimonium which is cited as evidence for this is far from unambiguous.(28) Later, but more securely, Archytas' music-theoretic proposition that `no mean number may be interpolated in an epimoric interval' depends upon the idea of numbers which are prime to each other.(29) It does not seem difficult to assign the discovery of perfect numbers to Pythagoreans, at least from the time of Archytas (c. 400 B.C.), nor to hold that, if the concept was current in the Academy of Euclid's and Euphorion's generations, it owed its existence there to the thought of Pythagoras' later followers.

THE MOPSOPIA: THE PERFECT DISMEMBERMENT?

`... Equal to his (or their) [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], with the result that they are called "perfect".'(30) Do we know anything at all about the context?

The only clue is the title of the work, Mopsopia. Euphorion's Suda biography tells us that this was the title of one of the poet's [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] so, if it was the name of a whole poetry book, it could have contained poems with their own individual titles); it adds that it dealt with Attica. Fr. 34 P. runs through some of Attica's earlier names. Another fragment seems to have dealt with the Orphic legend of the death of Dionysus at the hands of the Titans: fr 36 P., from Philodemus, is evidence for some treatment of the story that Dionysus, in one of his incarnations, was torn apart by Titans and reassembled by Rhea.(31) This is perhaps to be brought into relation with fr. 13 P,, cited from the Dionysus, apparently on the roasting of the dismembered god and his burial in Delphi.(32) That the Dionysus was perhaps part of the Mopsopia was suggested in dissertations by Schultze and Scheidweiler and has been repeated with approval since then.(33)

[GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] seems to recall Euclid's [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] punning on [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] could be `songs' or `limbs', but the latter is much easier to understand with [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] are also linked in the sense of body-parts in anatomical contexts.(34) We saw, too, that Nicomachus and, following him,[Elias], exemplified hyperperfect and defective numbers by analogies with bodies which had too many or too few parts; so it seems possible that Euphorion himself used some sort of analogy between perfect numbers and body parts. In view of the poem's known connection with Dionysus, Barigazzi suggested that our fragment might have to do with his dismemberment at the hands of the Titans.(35) The translation would then be something like, `(pieces) equal to (the number of) his limbs'--i.e. he was divided limb from limb, piecemeal, [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], the standard term in accounts of human dismemberment. An intriguing idea: could Euphorion be suggesting that the murderous Titans cut the god into a `perfect' number of pieces?

He is being unorthodox, if so. The number of pieces into which Dionysus was cut was a topic of interest in the Dionysian mysteries. It was the number seven.(36) Proclus in his Timaeus commentary explains how the heart of Dionysus was the one part of him which was undivided, because the heart is the seat of indivisible [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. The rest was divided by the Titans into seven pieces, and Proclus quotes a line from [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (the Orphic rhapsodies) on the dismemberment of Dionysus by the Titans: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].(37) Firmicus Maternus also has a reference to the seven spits on which the god was roasted.(38)

If Euphorion's god was cut into a perfect number, can we reconcile the seven of the rhapsodies with a Euclidean perfect number? Could Dionysus have been cut into 6 + 1 (the heart) pieces rather than the 7 + 1 of the Orphic rhapsodies?(39) Another macabre possibility suggested to me by Edward Hussey is that he was cut into the Orphic number of seven pieces, and then that each piece was the cut into a further four, thus producing, not six, but the second perfect number, 28. And after that, the number of exotic forms of dismemberment which can be envisaged is limited only by the imagination of the reader. But why should a division into six pieces result in the designation [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]? The implication may be that Euphorion is offering an etymology for perfect numbers, If Barigazzi is right about the context, then one possibility comes to mind. The Dionysiac mysteries concerned with the death and rebirth of Dionysus were called [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Perhaps Euphorion is punning on [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (or even on the use of [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] in sacrifices to denote unblemished sacrifical victims?). [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] easy to pun on, and Plato makes a similar connection in Phaedr. 249c: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Does Euphorion mean that `perfect' numbers originated with the `perfect' dismemberment of Dionysus, henceforth celebrated in a rite called the [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]?

But this is only one possibility. Another is that the [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] are those of the assailants, not of the victim. The Titans and Giants had six hands each, according to Orph.Arg. [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] 517 [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (an adaptation of Hes Theog 150, on the hundred-handers Cottus, Briaereus, and Gyges). This is unusual: Titans and Giants are normally only endowed with the standard number of hands, and one wonders why the Orphic poet or his source made the change A third possibility, of course, is that the context in Euphorion is not about dismemberment at all, but (perhaps) concerns medicine--healing, or the sort of subject which might have justified the line's inclusion in a medical compilation. But there is little point in further speculation.

CONCLUSION

The foregoing was conjecture. There is no indication of context in the source who quotes the line, and nothing about Dionysus in the line itself. What is more important is the likelihood that here we have a poet in the middle of the third century B.C. referring to a mathematical notion which in extant literature can only be traced back as far as Euclid. Either Euphorion knows Euclid, in which case we have one of our earliest references, perhaps our very earliest, to the Elements; or he has picked up material which has already spread through the mathematical community, which is evidence for the pre-Euclidean existence of the idea of perfect numbers. But which?

(1) I should like to thank the three people who helped in the construction and criticism of this paper: David Fowler, Edward Hussey, and the anonymous referee of CQ.

(2) The fragment was not known to Powell. However I cite the other poetic fragments from Powell's Collectanea Alexandrine and testimonia for Euphorion's life from Van Groningen.

(3) D. H. Fowler, The Mathematics of Plato's Academy: A New Reconstruction (Oxford, 1987). The earliest reference to Euclid which he finds is presented on p. 208, and consists of ostraka from Elephantine in Upper Egypt, which deal with the results of El. 13.10 and 16 ([Pack.sup.2] 2323). Like our material, they come from the third quarter of the third century B.C. They do not follow our text of the Elements, but seem to constitute an attempt to work it through to the writer's own personal satisfaction.

(4) See A. Busse, Davidis Prolegomena et in Porphyrii Isagogen Commentarium (Berlin, 1904) = CAG XVIII.2. The discussion of perfect numbers is at pp. 22.18-35 Busse.

(5) The beginning of the text, including the section on perfect numbers, is represented only by the manuscripts Paris gr. 1939 and Monac. gr. 399; on the manuscripts see Westerink, Pseudo-Elias, pp. vii-viii.

(6) This is true of the first five perfect numbers--Nicomachus knew the first four--but it ceases to be true afterwards: see T. Heath, History of Greek Mathematics (henceforward HGM) (Oxford, 1921; repr. New York, 1981), vol. I, p. 74.

(7) [Elias] has been using different verbs, [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], and the like.

(8) Euclidis Elementa, ed. I. L. Heiberg, rev. E. S. Stamatis (Leipzig, 1970), vol. II, p. 105.

(9) Heath, HGM, vol. I, pp. 98-9.

(10) David 8.10, Nicomachus 1.15.1.

(11) Callimachus' Cleombrotus epigram (AP 7.471 = Ep. 23 Pf. = HE 1273-6) in [Elias] 12.5; David, p. 31.30-3 Busse. Theognis 175-6 in [Elias] 13.4; David, p. 32.21-2; Elias, p. 15.17-18 Busse in CAG XVIII.1. There are also tags from the tragedians and Homer.

(12) ([Elias] 19.23) cites Ap. Rhod. 3.1323, also in Et. Mag. 43.47, s.v. akaiva.

(13)E.g. [Iamblichus] Theologoumena Arithmeticae, ed. V. de Falco (Leipzig, 1975), listing [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (p. 50.2-3) and [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (p. 48.21) among the names for six.

(14) When the sum of the sequence of duplications starting from one (1, 2, 4, and so on) is a prime number, then that number; multiplied by the last term of the series, will result in a perfect number. The first two perfect numbers are produced thus: 6 = (1 + 2) x 2, and 28 = (1 + 2 + 4) x 4. On the other hand 1 + 2 + 4 + 8 results in 15, which is not a prime number, so that 15 x 8 = 120, which is not perfect.

(15) See Heath, HGM, vol. I, pp. 74-5 and his commentary on Euclid El. 7 Def. 23 and 9.36.

(16) See on his Life and Works in Dictionary of Scientific Biography, ed. C. C. Gillespie (New York, 1970-8), vol. II, pp. 414-37 (I. Bulmer-Thomas), esp. pp. 414-15, and on the transmission of the Elements, ibid., pp. 437-59 (J. Murdoch), esp. pp. 437-8. Our main sources are Proclus, In Primum Euclidis, p. 68.6-23 Friedlein, and Pappus Collection VII.35, II, p. 678.10-12 Hultsch.

(17) Pace P. Treves, Euforione e la storia ellenistica (Milan, 1955), pp. 48-54; see the review by P. M. Fraser, Gnomon 28 (1956), 580-1.

(18) See Euphorion's Suda entry ([Epsilon] 3801) and (a reference to Athenian citizenship) Helladius ap. Photius cod. 279 p. 532 b18 B = Testt. 1 and 3 Van Groningen; for Euclid, see Bulmer-Thomas, art. cit. (n. 16).

(19) An. 1.3 (PCGV 184-5 Euangelus).

(20) For instance, see Carm. Aur. 47; Sext. Emp. Adv. Math. 7.94; Hierocles on Carm. Aur. FPG I p. 465 Mullach.

(21) Theon of Smyrna, p. 46.12-13, Nicom. ap. Iamblich. Theol. Arithm., p. 44.15.

(22) W. Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Cambridge, MA, 1972), p. 431, n. 28; AP 14.1; Athen. 1.4e.

(23) C. M. Taisbak, `Perfect Numbers--A Mathematical Pun?', Centaurus 20 0976), 269-75.

(24) O. Becket, `The Theory of Odd and Even in the Ninth Book of Euclid's Elements, An Attempt to Reconstruct its Original Form', trans, in The Graduate Philosophy Journal 16. 1 (1992), 87-110, originally published as `Die Lehre yom Geraden und Ungeraden im neunten Buch der euklidischen Eiemente', Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Mathematik, Astronomic und Physik Abteilung B3 (1934), 533-53.

(25) Burkert (n. 22 above), p. 435.

(26) On Pythagorean `pebble arithmetic', see C. A. Huffman, Philolaus of Croton, Pythagorean and Presocratic (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 185-6.

(27) Arist. P.A. 14, p. 73a 40-b1 and II 13, p. 96a 35-7; Top. [Theta] 2, p. 157a 39; Met. A 6, 987b 33.

(28) Heath, HGM, vol. I, p. 72; O. Becker, Des mathematische Denken der Antike (Gotttingen, 1957), pp. 46-7 asserts that Philolaus mentioned prime numbers The reference to Philolaus is in Speusippus ap. Theol. Arithm. 82.10 (= Vors. [I.sup.3], p. 304.5, but not included in the sixth edition), but it is far from clear that it is truly well-informed; see Huffman (n. 26 above), pp. 359-63. Thymaridas is also supposed to have made use of the notion, Iambl. In Nicom., p. 27.4.

(29) See B. L. Van der Waerden, Science Awakening (Groningen, 1954), vol. I, p. 111. He argues that the contents of the whole of Book VII of the Elements should be attributed to the Pythagoreans before Archytas.

(30) [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] could, of course, refer to the third-person singular: KB I.602 and Schwyzer II.204-5.

(31) Philodemus De Piet. 44, p. 16.1 Gomp. = Orph. fr. 36 Kern: [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (suppl. Gomperz et Wilamowitz, Hermes 33 [1898], 521).

(32) [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] See M. L. West, The Orphic Poems (Oxford, 1983), pp. 150-2, 160-3. According to West, it was the Orphic account which included the grave of Dionysus in Delphi and the preservation of the separate heart (cf. also Call. fr. 517/643 Pf.), and the non-Orphic one which had him fitted back together `on the same body or at least on the same skeleton'. So both Orphic and non-Orphic accounts are known to Euphodon.

(33) G. Schultze, Euphorionea (Diss. Stralgburg, 1888), p. 57; E Scheidweiler, Euphorionis Fragmenta (Diss. Bonn, 1908), p. 27.

(34) Plat. Leg. 795e [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] Arist. HA. 486a 9ff. [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

(35) A. Barigazzi, `Il Dionysos di Euforione', in Miscellanea di Studi Alessandrini (Torino, 1963), pp. 416-54. He discusses this fragment on pp. 447- 8: `Una citazione di Euforione [GREEK TEXT NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] relativa, mi par rosa sicura, allo squartamento di Barco, al quale vien riportato secondo una tradizione pitagorica l'origine dei numeri perfetti.'

(36) Osiris, in many respects the prototype of the dismembered Dionysus, is said to have been cut up into fourteen pieces, a number given a lunar interpretation; but other traditions allude to 16, 26, and even 42 pieces (see Plut. Mor. 358a and 368a, and Gwyn Griffiths' commentary on De Iside et Osiride, pp. 338-9).

(37) Proclus on Plat. Tim. 35a (II 145.18 Diehl, Orph. fr. 210 Kern).

(38) Firm. Mat. De Error. 8.2: alii crudeli morte caesura aut in olla decoquunt aut septem veribus corporis mei membra lacerata subfigunt, cited in A. Henrichs, Die Phoinikika des Lollianos (Bonn, 1972), pp. 67-8, n. 59.

(39) See W. Burkert, Homo Necans: The Anthropology of Ancient Greek Sacrificial Ritual and Myth (Berkeley/Los Angeles, 1983), p. 105 with n. 11 on forms of dismemberment which are relics of hunting rituals.
COPYRIGHT 1998 Cambridge University Press
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 1998 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Title Annotation:Supplementum Hellenisticum
Author:Lightfoot, J.L.
Publication:The Classical Quarterly
Date:Jan 1, 1998
Words:5097
Previous Article:Doubts about other minds and the science of physiognomics.
Next Article:P. Sulpicius' law to recall exiles, 88 B.C.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2019 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters