Printer Friendly

Academic freedom in America today: a Marxist view.

Three brief case studies: in 1915, Scott Nearing, a socialist professor of economics, was fired from the University of Pennsylvia for publicly opposing the use of child labor in coal mines. With an influential mine owner on the Board of Trustees, the president of the university decided he had to let Nearing go. As far as I can discover, he is the first professor fired from an American university for his radical beliefs and activities.

Some have argued that this honor belongs to Edward Bemis, who was dismissed from the University of Chicago in 1894. A major charge in this case was that Bemis had the poor judgment to hold discussions with union leaders during the famous Pullman railroad strike of that year. In a letter to the president of the University of Chicago, Bemis admitted that he had talked to the union officials, but--he insisted--only with the purpose of urging them to give up the strike. It didn't help. The strike went on--and the dismissal stuck. However, in light of Bemis' admission, I find it difficult to view him as the first radical to lose his job because of his political beliefs. That honor belongs to Nearing. This doesn't mean that the universities were tolerant earlier. Before Nearing, there simply were no radical professors.

Second, in 1940 the Rapp-Coudert Committee of the New York State legislature began its infamous investigation of subversives in the Municipal College System (now City University of New York-CUNY). By 1974, over 40 professors were fired or did not get their contracts renewed either because they were communists or because they refused to divulge their political beliefs and connections.

Third, in 1978 Joel Samoff was denied tenure by the political science department of the University of Michigan. Though he had published widely and was about to receive the university's Distinguished Service Award for outstanding contributions to the scholarly life of the university, he was faulted for not publishing enough in orthodox political science journals and for using an unscientific Marxist approach to his subject matter.

In each case, a professor's right to puruse truth in his own way was abrogated. In the Nearing case, the ax was wielded by the university's higher administration. For the CUNY 40, it was the government which was primarily responsible for the blow that befell them, while Samoff's academic demise resulted from a decision taken by a majority of his own colleagues.

Where does academic freedom lie in all this? While there is general agreement that academic freedom involves the right of teachers and students to investigate any topic they wish and to freely discuss, teach, and publish their conclusions, there is an anguished debate over where to draw the line (nowhere is everthing allowed) and, more particularly, over who should be allowed to do it. Where does the threat to academic freedom come from? The case against government interference in academic decision-making is most easily made and probably most widely supported: academic freedom is assured when the government adopts a hands-off policy toward the university.

Many dissatisfied professors and students, however maintain that a greater danger to academic freedom today comes from university presidents and boars of trustees who ty to impose their values and judgments on the entire university community. Still others, including such victims of peer evaluation as Joel Samoff, would argue it is faculty bias which does the most damage, that without a sincere toleration of unorthodox approaches on the part of the professorate there can be no thoroughgoing academic freedom.

The situation is more complicated still, for even the people who advocate government interference in university affairs often do so--in their words--"to protect academic freedom," in this case against the deceivers and manipulators of youth. In short, everyone is in favor of academic freedom; only the emphasis and enemies are differet. In 1978, when I was denied a job as chairman of the government department at the University of Maryland because of my Marxist political views, I called this denial an attack on my academic freedom. The faculty, who had chosen me for the job, also said their academic freedom had been infringed upon. Students, who wanted to study with me, made the same claim. President John Toll, who rejected me, insisted he was acting on behalf of academic freedom, his academic freedom to do what he though best in disregard of all outside pressures. And many state politicians, whose threats of financial retribution against the univesity constituted the most powerful of these outside pressures, likewise spoke of defending academic freedom against the likes of me.

The problem of sorting out the various uses of "academic freedom" is both very easy and terribly complex: easy, if it is simply a matter of taking a stand, of choosing the notion of "academic freedom" which is most compatible with one's own values and declaring other uses illegitimate. It becomes complex if we try to explore the relations between these different uses to discover what as a group they reveal about the conditions they are intended to describe. It is by taking this latter path that I hope to cast some light on the state of academic freedom in America today.

The time-honored way of breaking out of the confusion which surrounds the discussion of academic freedom is to label what has hitherto passed as a definition as the ideal, and to add the words, "Unfortunately, it doesn't always apply." The implication, of course, is that this is what most people want, and that actual practice is close and closing in on the ideal. Focusing on the ideal in this way, practice can be short-changed. What actually happens is viewed teleologically, in terms of what one thinks it is going to become eventually, in time, with patience and more propagandizing of the ideal. The possibility that the gap between the actual and the ideal is more or less fixed and that the ideal may even play a role in keeping it so is hardly entertained, and can't be so long as what occurs is not examined on its own terms and within its real social and political context. In any case, the confusion over the different uses of academic freedom can never be sorted out so long as the discussion remains on the abstract level of ideas. For this, we must keep our feet on solid ground, and find out who is doing what to whom and why.

The locus of our study, of course, will be the university. And not just any university, but the university in capitalist society. Can't we just examine the nature of universities in general? I think not. Why not should be evident if we look no further than the big-business dominated boards of trustees of all our major universities. if we were studying institutions of higher learning in a foreign country and discovered that a majority of the members of all their boards of trustees were generals, we would not hesitate to make certain conclusions about the character and aim of education there. Yet even people who know that our boards of trustees are run by a business elite seldom question why this is so or try to think through what follows from this fact. Are businesspeople really more clever than the rest of us, or more public spirited, or more concerned with the development of rational and critical thought? If not, we must try to understand what capitalists want from the university and what they do there, and how all this relates to academic freedom.

Capitalism is a formof society where the means of production are privately owned, and all production decisions are made on the basis of what will earn the largest profits for owners. So much holds true for the entire history of our republic. But the American capitalist system has also undergone a number of major changes. Marxist economist Sam Bowles points out that the capitalist economy and riding a bicycle have one important thing in common: in both, forward motion is necessary for stability. (Perhaps someone should point this out to Ronald Reagan.) As capitalism grows and changes so does the nature of its requirements from education, as, indeed, from other sectors of capitalist life.

Among the major developments in American capitalism over the last 100 years are the following: with the growth of technology, the amount of capital investment going to workers in the form of wages has decreased as a percentage of total investment, leading to a general and long-term squeeze on profits (surplus-value, of which profit is a portion, is produced by labor; hence, a relatively smaller percentage of investment going to labor means a constricted base for profits); the percentage of the workforce which is self employed (entrepreneurs and professionals) has gone down from 40 percent to 10 percent; in the same period, the number of managers and professionals on salaries (chiefly employed by big business) has increased sevenfold; in big business, complex hierarchies have developed that determine power, status, and salary; more jobs require minimal skills; an intensification of the division of labor has led to an increased fragmentation of tasks for both white- and blue-collar workers, decreasing the degree of control that each individual has over his or her job; mainly in order to maintain profits, the government has come to play a more direct role in running the economy on behalf of the capitalist class; and ideology--that is, one-sided, partial, essentially mystifying interpretations of reality--has spread from the factory to the media, market, and schools, chiefly as a means of disguising the increasingly obvious procapitalist bias of the state.

The major changes that have occured in American higher education during the last 100 years reflect these developments in the capitalist mode of production, and have operated in general to facilitate the efficient functioning of the new capitalist order. For example, whereas in 1870 only 2 percent of the 18-21 age group went to college, today it is about 50 percent. The liberal arts and classics which formed the core of the old university curriculum have been replaced by science, math, public administration, business, and other vocational training. In both the natural and social sciences, universities have assumed more and more research and development tasks for private industry, upping their profits by reducing their necessary costs.

Increasingly, university life has been organized on the basis of a complex system of tests, grades, and degrees, so that people know exactly where they fit, what they deserve, what has to be done to rise another notch on the scale, and so on. Discounting--as most educators do--their negative effects on scholarship, critical thinking, and collegialtiy, these practices have succeeded in instilling a new discipline and respect for hierarchy, lowering students' expectations, and generally in creating a sense that you get what you work for and have talent for--and, therefore, that failure is due to some personal fault (laziness, stupidity, or bad will).

Overseeing this reorganization of the academy, codifying its ends and rationalizing its means, dispensing incentives, cost accounting, building bridges to the "community" (chiefly business leaders and politicians) is the work of a vastly expanded cast of professional managers. At Columbia University, for example, in the period 1948-68, the faculty grew by 50 percent, the student body by 100 percent, and the administration by 900 percent.

Of all the ideas which help keep democratic capitalism in the United States functioning as smoothly as it does, none is more important than the idea of "equality of opportunity." Here, too, the university has a special role to play. It seems that people are willing to live with great social and economic inequalities equalities if they believe they had, or have, or will have the chance to make it up, or even that their children will have such a chance. In the nineteenth century, the belief in equality of opportunity was fed chiefly by the existence of "free" land in the West. When the frontier closed, this dream was kept alive by the possibility of starting a small business which, with a little luck and hard work, might one day make you rich. Now that 9 out of every 10 small businesses end in failure (according to U.S. Commerce Department statistics), it is our relatively open system of higher education which serves as living evidence for the existence of equality of opportunity.

For universities to play their appointed role in this capitalist drama, it is not enough that everyone who wants to get an education be able to get into a university. In both its structure and content, higher education must appear to give everyone a more or less equal chance to prepare for the best jobs. Should the universities be perceived as vocational schools, providing low-level skills and indoctrinating students with the values and attitudes deemed important by their future capitalist employers, as a simple continuation of the tracking system already begun in high schools, the crucial ideological work of the university in promoting belief in the existence of a real equality of opportunity would suffer irreparable damage.

The university's role in helping to justify democratic capitalism carries over, as we might expect, to the content of its courses. Particularly today, with the government's more direct involvement in the economy on the side of the capitalists and so many young members of the working class in college with time to read and think about it, there is a great need for ever more sophisticated rationalizations for the status quo. In this effort, the university must maintain the appearance of allowing all points of view, including some critical of capitalism, to freely contest. Otherwise, the ideas which emerge from universities would be tainted, viewed as propaganda rather than "knowledge" and "science," and have less hold on people. Not only students would be affected, but also the general public, many of whose beliefs and prejudices receive their legitimation as value-free social science by academic decree.

Finally, to complete our list of the main ways in which higher education serves capitalism in the modern period, we should mention that the universities provide local capitalists with a reserve army of low paid, nonunionized, part-time workers, while at the same time offering a kind of custodial care for young people who cannot find jobs, becoming in Ira Shor's apt phrase "warehouses for unneeded workers." Here, too, students will only willingly accept these degrading roles and conditions if they believe they are receiving a real education and being prepared for something better.

Does all this mean that the university is not a place where knowledge and skills get passed on from one generation to the next, and where some people teach and others actually learn how to think more critically? Not at all. Like universities in all periods and virtually all societies, American universities embody, to one degree or another, all the fine qualities which are paraded in Commencement Day speeches. Unfortunately, these speeches neglect to mention other functions which clearly stamp our universities as products of capitalist society, and any attempt to grasp the dynamics of the present situation must begin by focusing on these historically specific qualities.

The time has come t reintroduce the idea of academic freedom and to see how it works. The first thing which strikes us from the above account is that American universities require a little critical thought, which means a few critical teachers, which means too, a little academic freedom for them to work, in order for universities to function as they are meant to and have to in capitalist society. The presence of some radical professors helps to legitimate the bourgeois ideology which comes out of universities as "social science" and the universities themselves as something more than training centers. So a few radical professors are necessary to make the point that real freedom of thought, discussion, and so on exist and that people in the university have the opportunity to hear all sides in the major debates of the day.

But a key question is: At what point do a few radical professors become too many? For the presence of radicals in universities at a time of burgeoning working-class enrollment and a declining economy constitutes a real and growing threat to the capitalist system. In the story of the emperor's new clothes, it didn't take many voices to convince the crowd that the emperor was naked. At a time of deepening economic crisis, the promises of capitalism are no less vulnerable.

Given the need for some radical professors and the dangers of too many, the debate over where to draw the line, who should draw it, and on the basis of what criteria goes on continually. It goes on in government, in university administrations, and among the faculty in almost every university department.

Because the language in which these questions are posed is different on each level, even participants are not always aware that they are involved in the same debate. Without explicit coordination, using apparently different criteria and procedures, and while lost in their own internecine disputes over turf and power, the government, university administrations, and departmental facilities are all taking part in the same balancing act.

Viewed from the perspective of their victims (of those who suffer because they fall on the other side of the line), however, the practice of academic freedom in our universities appears as a kind of policing mechanism which operates on three levels. On the level of government, its means (repressive laws, administrative harassment, threats to reduce funding, etc.) and ends are pretty evident, though even here there is some attempt to disguise the ends in terms of preserving students' academic freedom from the predations of deceptive radical professors. For the administration, the disguise takes the forms of preserving university autonomy from direct government interference on one hand, and making universities run smoothly (radicals tend to make waves) on the other. At the faculty level, this "internal policing," in the words of Marxist scholar Milton Fisk, takes the form of making so-called objective, value-neutral decisions on what constitutes political science or economics or philosophy, and which journals in each discipline warrant the academic Good Housekeeping Seal of Approval--so that publishing elsewhere, which usually means in radical journals, doesn't count for promotion, tenure, and the like.

Only on the first level, that of government, is academic repression expressed in political terms, as an effort to keep radicals or Marxists out of the university because of their political beliefs. Hence, whenever governments are forced to act against radicals, the ideological work of the university, which relies so heavily on the assumption of tolerance, is seriously jeopardized. Better by far if university administrators, using institutional arguments, refuse to hire radical professors or turn them down for tenture. Best of all, of course, is when departmental faculties, using what appear to be purely professional criteria, take the initiative themselves. Consequently, and as a general rule, politicians get involved in academic repression, or threaten to do so, only when university administration fail to act "responsibly," or give signs that they are about to; while administrators overrule their faculty on this matter only when it is the latter who have failed to act "responsibly."

In distinguishing among the forms of academic repression peculiar to the government, university administrators, and departmental faculties, I do not mean to suggest that these three levels are autonomous. Quite the contrary. The influence of the government on university administrations, for example--through appointing presidents and boards of trustees, determining budgets, setting research priorities, licensing programs, etc.--is so overwhelming that one scholar, Michael Brown, would have us view administrations in public universities as part of the state apparatus. The situation in what are still called "private" universities differs only in degree. Nor do I wish to play down the ties of interests and values which bind government, university administrations, and most departmental faculties to the capitalist class, a connection which Milton Fisk tries to highlight by designating university professors a "class of functionaries" with a special servitor relationship to capitalists. I have been chiefly concerned, however, to examine how the contradictory functions of the capitalist university (in particular, educating, socializing, and legitimating capitalist social relations) result in different kinds of academic repression which turn out, upon analysis, to be different aspects of the same thing; and this just because of the intimate ties (sketched by Brown, Fisk, and others) among the capitalist class, the government, university administrations, and most faculty.

As regards academic freedom, what I have been arguing is that a kind of academic freedom already exists. It takes the form of a three-tiered mechanism of academic repression. It is the way this repression functions, for whom and against what. The underside of who is allowed to teach is who cannot; just as what cannot be studied is organically related to what can be studied. Setting this ever changing boundary is the act of freedom of some which determines the kind (muted) and degree (very little) of freedom available to all. Unfortunately, academic freedom, interpreted as the actual practice of freedom in the academy, its expression as repression, is not quite what we always thought it was. What, then, can be said about what we always thought it was, or what is often referred to as the ideal of academic freedom?

First, it is clear that as long as the capitalist class controls the universities, which is to say as long as capitalism exists, the gap between the ideal of academic freedom and its practice (described above) is more or less fixed. But I have also suggested that this ideal itself may play a role in keeping this gap fixed, that rather than part of the solution the ideal of academic freedom may be part of the problem. How can this be so? Partly, it is so because the ideal of academic freedom helps to disguise and distort an essentially repressive practice by presenting it as an imperfect version ofwhat should be. Putting what everyone is said to favor in the front (and at the start) relegates what actually exists to the role of a passing qualification. Viewed in this way (and in this order), the dynamics of who is doing what to whom and why, together with the structural reforms needed to change things, can never be understood.

Second, beginning as the admittedly inadequate description of real events, the ideal of academic freedom gradually substitutes itself as an explanation of what is happening that is so feeble that, with minor qualifications, all the worst villains can embrace it. Though everyone may favor academic freedom, it is in the nature of ideals--it is said--that they can never be fully realized. Something similar occurs with the ideal of consumer sovereignty in which the assumed goal of the exercise replaces and then helps to explain what people actually do in supermarkets, where they generally choose products that they have been socialized to want. Likewise, the ideal of democracy plays a similar twofold role in respect to what happens in real elections, in which money and control of media play the decisive roles. In every instance, asserting a valued goal becomes the means for misrepresenting and explaining away a reality that has little to do with it, except insofar as this reality requires for its continued existence people's misuse of this goal. In other words, it is only because most people in the university misunderstand academic repression in terms of an imperfect academic freedom that academic freedom can continue to function os effectively as academic repression. If the practice of academic freedom in capitalism is academic repression, the ideal of academic freedom is the ideology that both permits and provides a cover for its occurrece.

So much allows from privileging the qualities of academic freedom as an ideal, but the contribution that the ideal of academic freedom makes to preserving the status quo also comes from its narrow focus on freedom. Talk of freedom, whether in the marketplace, in politics, or in the academy, assumes equality in the conditions which permit people to use their freedom or the irrelevance of such conditions. For freedom is not just about wanting something, but includes the ability to do so or have what one wants. It is a want embodied in a practice, but, unlike the simple want, the practice requires the existence of certain conditions. Unfortunately, in a class-divided society, such conditions are never equal and always relevant. simple put, some people have the money, jobs, education, and so forth to act freely, and others do not. In every case, the priveleged few also benefit from a ready-made rationalization of their privileges: they are simply making use of their freedom. Let others, they say, try to do as much.

In the academy, the people with power use their freedom to repress radicals in the ways described. If the police mechanisms embodied in the practice of academic freedom give them the means to do this, it is the ideal of academic freedom which gives them an effective way of rationalizing it, hence the constant patter about exercising their academic freedom as they go about their work of repression. In the university, as throughout capitalist society, a commitment to freedom in the absence of an equally strong commitment to social justice carries with it the seeds of even greater injustice. For the ideal of academic justice to take its place alongside the ideal of academic freedom, however, we shall have to await the coming of a society that no longer needs its universities to help reproduce and rationalize existing inequalities, that is, a socialist society.

So far I have examined the role that the ideal of academic freedom plays in keeping things as they are, but now I am only too pleased to admit that this ideal also plays a part in helping to change them. That is, at the same time that the ideal of academic freedom hides, distorts, and helps to rationalize academic repression by government, university administrations, and departmental faculties, it also opens up a little space and provides some justification for the presentation of critical opinion. Rhetorically and occasionally procedurally, it also serves as a modest defense for radical teachers who avail themselves of this space. While wishing doesn't make it so and error exacts compound interest, what people believe to be true (even if false) and what they consider good (even if impossible) are not without influence. If only through constant repetition, liberal cant occasionally takes hold, particularly on younger members of the academy, producing a subspecies of academic freedom groupies, people too afraid to act upon their ideas but willing to support those who do. With the help of the few real exceptions, liberals who try to incorporate their beliefs into their daily lives (a self-destructive impulse for all but the most established scholars), the ideal of academic freedom sometimes plays a progressive role in the struggle to extend the boundaries of what can be studied in our universities.

The ideal of academic freedom, vague, unclear, contradictory, but repeated often enough, also exercises, in my view, a very general restraining influence on what the perpetrators of academic repression are able and even willing to do. It is not always true that it is better to deal with honest villains than with hypocritical ones. In our understandable disgust with their hypocrisy many radical critics have neglected to look for its positive side. The complex and occasionally humanizing influence of hypocrisy on hypocrites, in the university as indeed throughout capitalist society, requires further, serious examination.

Finally, and most important, the ideal of academic freedom also helps contribute to the development of critical thinking in the university insofar as it contains within itself elements of such thinking. At its best this means recognizing, as part of the ideal, how the conditions of modern capitalist society have turned the practice of academic freedom into academic repression and used the ideal to cover its tracks. A critically constituted ideal contains within it the conditions of its own misuse as well as the structural changes necessary to reverse this process. Saved from displays of moral outrage, we are freed to work for academic freedom by helping to build the democratic socialist conditions that are necessary for it to exist. In developing this expanded understanding of the ideal of academic freedom, in sharing it in the university and with the public at large, we are beginning the work of putting it into practice. Academic freedom, by this interpretation, lives and grows in the conscious struggle for a socialist society.

Unfortunately, none of these progressive trends are dominant. At present, they are all subordinate to the role played by academic freedom in helping to police the university, and deserve our attention only once this central role has been made clear. Otherwise, there is a danger of falling victim to all the distortions mentioned above and even contributing to them. But once the capitalist context in which academic freedom appears has been laid out, once its main function in this context is understood, its other role in helping to undermine capitalism requires equal attention.

In summary, academic freedom is about both freedom and repression, how they are linked to each other not only as opposites, but also as preconditions, effects and aspects, each of the other. Their proper order of treatment is first repression and then freedom. In this way, freedom is less distorted and the contribution that freedom (in its ideological form) makes to repression is minimized. The Marxist approach to academic freedom involves analyzing it as a practice, one inextricably tied to capitalist power relations, and as an accompanying ideology. This analysis embodies and helps to develop a new critical practice and an alternative vision which can also be subsumed under the broader notion of academic freedom.

What then is the situation today? What is the state of these contradictory tendencies in academic freedom in the winter of 1983/84? The first thing to remark is that there has been a considerable increase in the number of Marxist and other kinds of radical professors in the universities. Together with the growing crisis in capitalism and the inability of most bourgeois scholarship to explain it, this has led to the increased legitimacy of Marxist scholarship in practically every discipline. At the same time, there are also more radical professors not getting hired or tenured.

Probably the most striking development is a gradual breakdown of the three-tiered policing mechanism of academic repression described earlier. With a growth in the number of radical scholars and the increased legitimation of radical scholarship, the bottom tier, professors in the departments, is no longer excluding radicals with the regularity that it once was. I was jolted into recognizing this change by my experience at the University of Maryland, where a Search Committee made up of ten political scientists chose me, a Marxist, for their chair. I don't think this could have happened ten years earlier. And if this happened in political science, traditionally the most conservative of the social sciences, it is happening (though sometimes very slowly) in all disciplines, and in universities throughout the country (though many exceptions exist). In mine and other cases, this has simply forced university administrations and politicians (the second and third tiers) to take a more direct part in academic repression. But, as I have argued, there are limits to how much they can do without paying what is for them an unacceptable price in terms of legitimacy.

Consequently, on occasion, there have been important victories. Most recently, among the more prominent are Fred Block (Sociology, University of Pennsylvania) and Dick Walker (Geography, University of California-Berkeley), who received tenure, and Edwin Marquit (Physics, University of Minnesota) who won promotion--all after protracted struggles. Though the cards are stacked against us, they are not all dealt out, and the way a particular struggle is conducted can count.

In the coming period, I would expect to see--for reasons already given--a still greater increase in the number of radical teachers, a rise in the amount of academic repression (primarily by university administrators and to a lesser degree by the government), and--as a result of both--a continued weakening of the university's role as a legitimator of capitalist ideology. How these conflicting tendencies will finally work themselves out will of course depend far more on the social and political struggles of the larger society than on the positions we take within the university. Yet what we do as professors will count for something in the balance, so we must become better scholars, better critics, better teachers. We will also need courage, and we will need to be steadfast. Which brings me back to Scott Nearing.

On November 29, 1981, not quite two years before his death at the age of 100, Scott Nearing sent me a letter, which he asked me to share with everyone to whom it applies:

"To my comrades in the struggle for a kindlier and juster world, I send fraternal greetings. During the present period of worldwide change and unrest, study and teaching are particularly important. We as scholars have the right and duty to teach and impart what we believe in and what we have learned. The right to do this is the keystone of our profession. The need to do it arises whenever any authority challenges our responsibility to learn and communicate--to study and to teach. The present period offers scholars and students a challenge to meet and a part to play that may have vast consequences for the future of man. My salutations to the brave men and women who are opposing and resisting the forms of reaction, regression, and despotism in North America."
COPYRIGHT 1984 Monthly Review Foundation, Inc.
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 1984 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Ollman, Bertell
Publication:Monthly Review
Date:Mar 1, 1984
Words:5614
Previous Article:Comment: making history but not under circumstances chosen by ourselves.
Next Article:Coming of age.
Topics:

Terms of use | Privacy policy | Copyright © 2018 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters