Printer Friendly

A review on natural reality with physical equations.

1 Introduction

An observation on a physical phenomenon, or characters of a thing in the nature is the received information via hearing, sight, smell, taste or touch, i.e. sensory organs of the observer himself, little by little for human beings fulfilled with the reproducibility. However, it is difficult to hold the true face of a thing for human beings because he is analogous to a blind man in "the blind men with an elephant", a famous fable for knowing the nature. For example, let [[mu].sub.1], [[mu].sub.2], ..., [[mu].sub.n] be all observed and [v.sub.i], i [greater than or equal to] 1 unobserved characters on a particle P at time t. Then, P should be understood by

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (1.1)

in logic with an approximation [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] for P at time t. All of them are nothing else but Smarandache multispaces ([17]). Thus, P [approximately equal to] [P.sup.[omicron]] is only an approximation for its true face of P, and it will never be ended in this way for knowing P as Lao Zi claimed "Name named is not the eternal Name" in the first chapter of his TAO TEH KING ([3]), a famous Chinese book.

A physical phenomenon of particle P is usually characterized by differential equation

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (1.2)

in physics established on observed characters of [[mu].sub.1], [[mu].sub.2], ..., [[mu].sub.n] for its state function [psi](t, x) in [R.sup.4]. Usually, these physical phenomenons of a thing is complex, and hybrid with other things. Is the reality of particle P all solutions of (1.2) in general? Certainly not because (1.2) only characterizes the behavior of P on some characters of [[mu].sub.1], [[mu].sub.2], ..., [[mu].sub.n] at time t abstractly, not the whole in philosophy. For example, the behavior of a particle is characterized by the Schrodinger equation

i[??] [partial derivative][psi]/[partial derivative]t = -[[??].sup.2]/2m [[nabla].sup.2] [psi] + U [psi] (1.3)

in quantum mechanics but observation shows it in two or more possible states of being, i.e. superposition. We can not even say which solution of the Schrodinger equation (1.3) is the particle because each solution is only for one determined state. Even so, the understanding of all things is inexhaustible by (1.1).

Furthermore, can we conclude (1.2) is absolutely right for a particle P? Certainly not also because the dynamic equation (1.2) is always established with an additional assumption, i.e. the geometry on a particle P is a point in classical mechanics or a field in quantum mechanics and dependent on the observer is out or in the particle. For example, a water molecule [H.sub.2]O consists of 2 Hydrogen atoms and 1 Oxygen atom such as those shown in Fig. 1. If an observer receives information on the behaviors of Hydrogen or Oxygen atom but stands out of the water molecule [H.sub.2]O by viewing it a geometrical point, then such an observation is an out-observation because it only receives such coherent information on atoms H and O with the water molecule [H.sub.2]O.

If an observer is out the water molecule [H.sub.2]O, his all observations on the Hydrogen atom H and Oxygen atom O are the same, but if he enters the interior of the molecule, he will view a different sceneries for atom H and atom O, which are respectively called out-observation and in-observation, and establishes 1 or 3 dynamic equations on the water molecule [H.sub.2]O.

The main purpose of this paper is to clarify the natural reality of a particle with that of differential equations, and conclude that a solvable one characterizes only the reality of elementary particles but non-solvable system of differential equations essentially describe particles, such as those of baryons or mesons in the nature.

For terminologies and notations not mentioned here, we follow references [1] for mechanics, [5] for combinatorial geometry, [15] for elementary particles, and [17] for Smarandache systems and multispaces, and all phenomenons discussed in this paper are assumed to be true in the nature.

2 Out-observations

An out-observation observes on the external, i.e. these macro but not the internal behaviors of a particle P by human senses or via instrumental, includes the size, magnitudes or eigenvalues of states, ..., etc.

Certainly, the out-observation is the fundamental for quantitative research on matters of human beings. Usually, a dynamic equation (1.2) on a particle P is established by the principle of stationary action [delta]S = 0 with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (2.1)

in classical mechanics, where q(t), [??](t) are respectively the generalized coordinates, the velocities and L (q(t), [??](t)) the Lagrange function on the particle, and

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (2.2)

in field theory, where f is the state function and L the Lagrangian density with [[tau].sub.1], [[tau].sub.2] the limiting surfaces of integration by viewed P an independent system of dynamics or a field. The principle of stationary action [delta]S = 0 respectively induced the Euler-Lagrange equations

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (2.3)

in classical mechanics and field theory, which enables one to find the dynamic equations of particles by proper choice of L or L. For examples, let

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

Then we respectively get the Schrodinger equation (1.3) or the Dirac equation

(i[[gamma].sup.[mu]] [[partial derivative].sub.[mu]] - mc/[??]) [psi](t, x) = 0 (2.4)

for a free fermion [psi](t, x) and the Klein-Gordon equation

(1/[c.sup.2] [[partial derivative].sup.2]/[partial derivative][t.sup.2] - [[nabla].sup.2]) [psi](x, t) + [(mc/[??]).sup.2] [psi](x, t) = 0 (2.5)

for a free boson [psi](t, x) hold in relativistic forms by (2.3), where [??] = 6.582 x [10.sup.-22] MeV s is the Planck constant, c is the speed of light,

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

and [[gamma].sup.[mu]] = ([[gamma].sup.0], [[gamma].sup.1], [[gamma].sup.2], [[gamma].sup.3]) with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

with the usual Pauli matrices

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

Furthermore, let L = [square root of (-g R)], where R = [g.sup.[mu]v] [R.sub.[mu]v], the Ricci scalar curvature on the gravitational field. The equation (2.3) then induces the vacuum Einstein gravitational field equation

[R.sub.[mu]v] - 1/2 [g.sub.[mu]v] = R = 0. (2.6)

Usually, the equation established on the out-observations only characterizes those of coherent behaviors of all parts in a particle P. For example, a water molecule [H.sub.2]O obeys the Schrodinger equation (1.3), we assume its Hydrogen atom H and oxygen atom O also obey the Schrodinger equation (1.3) as a matter of course. However, the divisibility of matter initiates human beings to search elementary constituting cells of matter, i.e. elementary particles such as those of quarks, leptons with interaction quanta including photons and other particles of mediated interactions, also with those of their antiparticles at present ([14]), and unmatters between a matter and its antimatter which is partially consisted of matter but others antimatter ([8-19]). For example, a baryon is predominantly formed from three quarks, and a meson is mainly composed of a quark and an antiquark in the models of Sakata, or Gell-Mann and Ne'eman on hadron and meson, such as those shown in Fig. 2, where, [q.sub.i] [member of] {u, d, c, s, t, b} denotes a quark for i = 1, 2, 3 and [[bar.q].sub.2] [member of] {[bar.u], [bar.d], [bar.c], [bar.s], [bar.t], [bar.b]}, an antiquark. But a free quark was never found in experiments. We can not even conclude the Schrodinger equation (1.3) is the right equation (1.2) for quarks because it is established on an independent particle, can not be divided again in mathematics.

Then, why is it believed without a shadow of doubt that the dynamical equations of elementary particles such as those of quarks, leptons with interaction quanta are (1.3) in physics? It is because that all our observations come from a macro viewpoint, the human beings, not the particle itself, which rationally leads to H. Everett's multiverse interpretation on the superposition by letting parallel equations for the wave functions [psi](t, x) on positions of a particle in 1957 ([2]). We only hold coherent behaviors of elementary particles, such as those of quarks, leptons with interaction quanta and their antiparticles by (1.3), not the individual, and it is only an equation on those of particles viewed abstractly to be a geometrical point or an independent field from a macroscopic point, which leads physicists to assume the internal structures mechanically for hold the behaviors of particles such as those shown in Fig. 2 on hadrons. However, such an assumption is a little ambiguous in logic, i.e. we can not even conclude which is the point or the independent field, the hadron or its subparticle, the quark.

In fact, a point is non-divisible in geometry. Even so, the assumption on the internal structure of particles by physicists was mathematically verified by extending Banach spaces to extended Banach spaces on topological graphs [??] in [12]:

Let (V; +, x) be a Banach space over a field F and [??] a strong-connected topological graph with vertex set V and arc set X. A vector labeling [[??].sup.L] on [??] is a 1 - 1 mapping L : [??] [right arrow] V such that L : (u, v) - L(u, v) [member of] V for [for all](u, v) [member of] X([??]) and it is a [??]-flow if it holds with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

for [for all](u, v) [member of] X([??]), [for all]v [member of] V([??]), where 0 is the zero-vector in V.

For [??]-flows [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] on a topological graph [??] and [xi] [member of] F a scalar, it is clear that [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] are also [??]-flows, which implies that all [??]-flows on [??] form a linear space over F with unit O under operations + and x, denoted by [[??].sup.V], where O is such a [??]-flow with vector 0 on (u, v) for [for all](u, v) [member of] X([??]). Then, it was shown that [[??].sup.V] is a Banach space, and furthermore a Hilbert space if introduce

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

for [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], where [parallel]L(u, v)[parallel] is the norm of L(u, v) and <x, x> the inner product in V if it is an inner space. The following result generalizes the representation theorem of Frechet and Riesz on linear continuous functionals on [??]-flow space [[??].sup.V], which enables us to find [??]-flow solutions on linear equations (1.2).

Theorem 2.1([12]) Let T : [??].sup.V] [right arrow] C be a linear continuous functional. Then there is a unique [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] such that

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

for [for all][[??].sup.L] [member of] [[??].sup.V].

For non-linear equations (1.2), we can also get [??]-flow solutions on them if [??] can be decomposed into circuits. Theorem 2.2([12]) If the topological graph [??] is strong-connected with circuit decomposition

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

such that L([u.sup.v]) = [L.sub.i] (x) for [for all](u, v) [member of] X ([??]), 1 [less than or equal to] i [greater than or equal to] and the Cauchy problem

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

is solvable in a Hilbert space V on domain [DELTA] [subset] [R.sup.n] for integers 1 [greater than or equal to] i [greater than or equal to] l, then the Cauchy problem

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

such that L ([u.sup.v]) = [L.sub.i](x) for [for all](u,v) [member of] X([??]) is solvable for X [member of] [??].

Theorems 2.1-2.2 conclude the existence of [??]-flow solution on linear or non-linear differential equations for a topological graph [??], such as those of the Schrodinger equation (1.3), Dirac equation (2.4) and the Klein-Gordon equation (2.5), which all implies the rightness of physicists assuming the internal structures for hold the behaviors of particles because there are infinite many such graphs [??] satisfying conditions of Theorem 2.1-2.2, particularly, the bouquet [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], the dipoles [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] for elementary particles in [13].

3 In-observations

An in-observation observes on the internal behaviors of a particle, particularly, a composed particle P. Let P be composed by particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m]. Different from out-observation from a macro viewing, in-observation requires the observer holding the respective behaviors of particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m] in P, for instance an observer enters a water molecule [H.sub.2]O receiving information on the Hydrogen or Oxygen atoms H, O.

For such an observation, there are 2 observing ways:

(1) there is an apparatus such that an observer can simultaneously observe behaviors of particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., Pm, i.e. [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m] can be observed independently as particles at the same time for the observer;

(2) there are m observers [O.sub.1], [O.sub.2], ..., [O.sub.m] simultaneously observe particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m] i.e. the observer [O.sub.i] only observes the behavior of particle [P.sub.i] for 1 [less than or equal to] i [less than or equal to] m, called parallel observing, such as those shown in Fig. 3 for the water molecule [H.sub.2]O with m = 3.

Certainly, each of these observing views a particle in P to be an independent particle, which enables us to establish the dynamic equation (1.2) by Euler-Lagrange equation (2.3) for [P.sub.i], 1 [less than or equal to] i [less than or equal to] m, respectively, and then we can apply the system of differential equations

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (3.1)

for characterizing particle P in classical mechanics, or

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] (3.2)

for characterizing particle P in field theory, where the ith equation is the dynamic equation of particle [P.sub.i] with initial data [q.sub.0], [[??].sub.0] or [[psi].sub.0].

We discuss the solvability of systems (3.1) and (3.2). Let

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

for integers 1 [less than or equal to] i [less than or equal to] m. Then, the system (3.1) of equations is solvable if and only if

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. (3.3)

Otherwise, the system (3.1) is non-solvable. For example, let particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2] of masses M, m be hanged on a fixed pulley, such as those shown in Fig. 4.

Then, the dynamic equations on [P.sub.1] and [P.sub.2] are respectively

[P.sub.1] : [??] = g, x([t.sub.0]) = [x.sub.0] and [P.sub.2] : ddotx = -g, x([t.sub.0]) = [x.sub.0]

but the system

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

is contradictory, i.e. non-solvable.

Similarly, let [[psi].sub.i];(x, f) be the state function of particle [P.sub.i], i.e. the solution of

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

Then, the system (3.2) is solvable if and only if there is a state function [psi](x, f) on P hold with each equation of system (3.2), i.e.

[psi](x, t) = [[psi].sub.1](x, t) = ... = [psi]m(x, t), x [member of] [R.sup.3],

which is impossible because if all state functions [[psi].sub.i](x, f), 1 [less than or equal to] i [less than or equal to] m are the same, the particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m] are nothing else but just one particle. Whence, the system (3.2) is non-solvable if m [greater than or equal to] 2, which implies we can not characterize the behavior of particle P by classical solutions of differential equations.

For example, if the state function [[psi].sub.0](x, t) = [psi][H.sub.1](x, t) = [psi][H.sub.2](x, t) in the water molecule [H.sub.2]O for x [member of] [R.sup.3] hold with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

Then [psi].sub.O](x, t) = [psi][H.sub.1](x, t) = [psi][H.sub.1](x, t) concludes that

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

for [for all] x [member of] [R.sup.3] and t [member of] R, which implies that

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII],

a contradiction.

Notice that each equation in systems (3.1) and (3.2) is solvable but the system itself is non-solvable in general, and they are real in the nature. Even if the system (3.1) holds with condition (3.3), i.e. it is solvable, we can not apply the solution of (3.1) to characterize the behavior of particle P because such a solution only describes the coherent behavior of particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m]. Thus, we can not characterize the behavior of particle P by the solvability of systems (3.1) or (3.2). We should search new method to characterize systems (3.1) or (3.2).

Philosophically, the formula (1.1) is the understanding of particle P and all of these particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m] are inherently related, not isolated, which implies that P naturally inherits a topological structure [G.sup.L][P] in space of the nature, which is a vertex-edge labeled topological graph determined by:

V ([G.sup.L][P]) = {[P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m]), E ([G.sup.L][P]) = {[P.sub.i], [P.sub.j]|[P.sub.i] [intersection] [P.sub.j][not equal to] [empty set], 1 [less than or equal to] i [not equal to] j [less than or equal to] m}

with labeling

L: [P.sub.i] [right arrow] L([P.sub.i]) = [P.sub.i] and L: ([P.sub.i], [P.sub.j]) [right arrow] L([P.sub.i], [P.sub.j]) = [P.sub.i] [intersection] [P.sub.j]

for integers 1 [less than or equal to] i [not equal to] j [less than or equal to] m. For example, the topological graphs [G.sup.L][P] of water molecule [H.sub.2]O, meson and baryon in the quark model of Gell-Mann and Ne'eman are respectively shown in Fig. 5,

where O, H, [bar.q'], [q.sub.i] and [less than or equal to] i [less than or equal to] 3 obey the Dirac equation but O [intersection] H, q [intersection] q', [q.sub.k] [intersection] [q.sub.1] 1 [less than or equal to] k, l [less than or equal to] 3 comply with the Klein-Gordon equation.

Such a vertex-edge labeled topological graph [G.sup.L][P] is called [G.sup.L]-solufion of systems (3.1)-(3.2). Clearly, the global behaviors of particle P are determined by particles [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m]. We can hold them on [G.sup.L]-solution of systems (3.1) or (3.2). For example, let [u.sup.[v]] be the solution of equation at vertex v [member of] V([G.sup.L][P]) with initial value [u.sup.[v].sub.0] and [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] the initial [G.sup.L]-solution, i.e. labeled with [u.sup.[v].sub.0] at vertex v. Then, a [G.sup.L]-solution of systems (3.1) or (3.2) is sum-stable if for any number [epsilon] > 0 there exists [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] such that each [G.sup.L']-solution with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

exists for all t [greater than or equal to] 0 and with the inequality

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

holds, denoted by [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Furthermore, if there exists a number [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] such that every [G.sup.L'] [P]-solution with

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

satisfies

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

then the [G.sup.L][P]-solution is called asymptotically stable, denoted by [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]. Similarly, the energy integral of [G.sup.L]-solution is determined by

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

where [u.sup.G] is the [C.sup.2] solution of system

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII]

and [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII] with [O.sub.v] [subset] [R.sup.n] determined by the vth equation

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

All of these global properties were extensively discussed in [7-11], which provides us to hold behaviors of a composed particle P by its constitutions [P.sub.1], [P.sub.2], ..., [P.sub.m].

4 Reality

Generally, the reality is the state characters (1.1) of existed, existing or will exist things whether or not they are observable or comprehensible by human beings, and the observing objective is on the state of particles, which then enables us to find the reality of a particle. However, an observation is dependent on the perception of the observer by his organs or through by instruments at the observing time, which concludes that to hold the reality of a particle P can be only little by little, and determines local reality of P from a macro observation at a time t, no matter what P is, a macro or micro thing. Why is this happening because we always observe by one observer on one particle assumed to be a point in space, and then establish a solvable equation (1.2) on coherent, not individual behaviors of P. Otherwise, we get non-solvable equations on P contradicts to the law of contradiction, the foundation of classical mathematics which results in discussions following:

4.1 States of particles are multiverse

A particle P understood by formula (1.1) is in fact a multiverse consisting of known characters [[mu].sub.1], [[mu].sub.2], ..., [[mu].sub.n] and unknown characters [v.sub.k], k [greater than or equal to] 1, i.e. different characters characterize different states of particle P. This fact also implies that the multiverse exist everywhere if we understand a particle P with in-observation, not only those levels of I - IV of Max Tegmark in [24]. In fact, the infinite divisibility of a matter M in philosophy alludes nothing else but a multiverse observed on M by its individual submatters. Thus, the nature of a particle P is multiple in front of human beings, with unity character appeared only in specified situations.

4.2 Reality only characterized by non-compatible system

Although the dynamical equations (1.2) established on unilateral characters are individually compatible but they must be globally contradictory with these individual features unless all characters are the same one. It can not be avoided by the nature of a particle P. Whence, the non-compatible system, particularly, non-solvable systems consisting of solvable differential equations are suitable tools for holding the reality of particles P in the world, which also partially explains a complaint of Einstein on mathematics, i.e. as far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality, they are not certain; and as far as they are certain, they do not refer to reality because the multiple nature of all things.

4.3 Reality really needs mathematics on graph

As we know, there always exists a universal connection between things in a family in philosophy. Thus, a family F of things naturally inherits a topological graph [G.sup.L][F] in space and we therefore conclude that

F = [G.sup.L][F] (4.1)

in that space. Particularly, if all things in F are nothing else but manifolds [M.sub.T]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2], [x.sub.3]; t) of particles P determined by equation

[f.sub.T]([x.sub.1], [x.sub.2], [x.sub.3]; t) = 0, T [member of] F (4.2)

in [R.sup.3] x R, we get a geometrical figure [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], a combinatorial field ([6]) for F. Clearly, the graph [G.sup.L][F] characterizes the behavior of F no matter whether the system (4.2) is solvable or not. Calculation shows that the system (4.2) of equations is non-solvable or not dependent on

[MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII].

Particularly, if [MATHEMATICAL EXPRESSION NOT REPRODUCIBLE IN ASCII], the system (4.2) is non-solvable and we can not just characterize the behavior of F by the solvability of system (4.2). We must turn the contradictory system (4.2) to a compatible one, such as those shown in [10] and have to extend mathematical systems on graph [G.sup.L][F] ([12]) for holding the reality of F.

Notice that there is a conjecture for developing mathematics in [4] called CC conjecture which claims that any mathematical science can be reconstructed from or turned into combinatorization. Such a conjecture is in fact a combinatorial notion for developing mathematics on topological graphs, i.e. finds the combinatorial structure to reconstruct or generalize classical mathematics, or combines different mathematical sciences and establishes a new enveloping theory on topological graphs for hold the reality of things F.

5 Conclusion

Reality of a thing is hold on observation with level dependent on the observer standing out or in that thing, particularly, a particle classified to out- or in-observation, or parallel observing from a macro or micro view and characterized by solvable or non-solvable differential equations, consistent with the universality principle of contradiction in philosophy. For holding on the reality of things, the out-observation is basic but the in-observation is cardinal. Correspondingly, the solvable equation is individual but the non-solvable equations are universal. Accompanying with the establishment of compatible systems, we are also needed to characterize those of contradictory systems, particularly, non-solvable differential equations on particles and establish mathematics on topological graphs, i.e. mathematical combinatorics, and only which is the appropriate way for understanding the nature because all things are in contradiction.

Submitted on June 18, 2015 / Accepted on June 20, 2015

References

[1.] Abraham R. and Marsden J. E. Foundation of Mechanics, 2nd ed. Addison-Wesley, Reading, MA, 1978.

[2.] Everett H. Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev.Mod.Phys., 1957, v. 29, 454-462.

[3.] Lu J. C. Fangfo Analyzing LAO ZHI--Explaining TAO TEH KING by TAI JI (in Chinese). Tuan Jie Publisher, Beijing, 2004.

[4.] Linfan Mao. Combinatorial speculation and combinatorial conjecture for mathematics. International J. Math. Combin., 2007, v. 1 (1), 1-19.

[5.] Linfan Mao. Combinatorial Geometry with Applications to Field Theory. The Education Publisher Inc., USA, 2011.

[6.] Linfan Mao. Combinatorial fields--an introduction. International J. Math. Combin., 2009, v. 3, 1-22.

[7.] Linfan Mao. Global stability of non-solvable ordinary differential equations with applications. International J. Math. Combin., 2013, v. 1, 1-37.

[8.] Linfan Mao. Non-solvable equation systems with graphs embedded in [R.sup.n]. in Proceedings of the First International Conference on Smarandache Multispace and Multistructure, The Education Publisher Inc., July 2013.

[9.] Linfan Mao. Geometry on [G.sup.L]-systems of homogenous polynomials. International J. Contemp. Math. Sciences, 2014, v. 9 (6), 287-308.

[10.] Linfan Mao. Mathematics on non-mathematics--A combinatorial contribution. International J.Math. Combin., 2014, v. 3, 1-34.

[11.] Linfan Mao. Cauchy problem on non-solvable system of first order partial differential equations with applications. Methods and Applications of Analysis, 2015, v. 22(2), 171-200.

[12.] Linfan Mao. Extended Banach [??]-flow spaces on differential equations with applications. Electronic J. Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 2015, v. 3 (2), 59-91.

[13.] Linfan Mao. A new understanding of particles by [??]-flow interpretation of differential equation, Progress in Physics, 2015, v. 11, 39-50.

[14.] Nambu Y. Quarks: Frontiers in Elementary Particle Physics. World Scientific Publishing, 1985.

[15.] Quang Ho-Kim and Pham Xuan Yem. Elementary Particles and Their Interactions. Springer-Verlag, Berlin Heidelberg, 1998.

[16.] Reid T. An inquiry into the human mind on the principles of common sense. in Brookes D., ed., Edinburgh University Press, 1997.

[17.] Smarandache F. Paradoxist Geometry. State Archives from Valcea, Rm. Valcea, Romania, 1969, and in Paradoxist Mathematics. Collected Papers (Vol. II). Kishinev University Press, Kishinev, 1997, pp. 5-28.

[18.] Smarandache F. A new form of matter--unmatter, composed of particles and anti-particles. Progress in Physics, 2005, v 1, 9-11.

[19.] Smarandache F. and Rabounski D. Unmatter entities inside nuclei, predicted by the Brightsen nucleon cluster model. Progress in Physics, 2006, v. 2, 14-18.

[20.] Tegmark M. Parallel universes. in Barrow J. D., Davies P. C. W. and Harper C. L., eds. Science and Ultimate Reality: From Quantum to Cosmos. Cambridge University Press, 2003.

Linfan Mao

Chinese Academy of Mathematics and System Science, Beijing 100190, P. R. China

E-mail: maolinfan@163.com
COPYRIGHT 2015 Progress in Physics
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2015 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Mao, Linfan
Publication:Progress in Physics
Article Type:Report
Date:Jul 1, 2015
Words:4856
Previous Article:On the possible mechanism of interaction of high-energy particles with nuclei.
Next Article:Abraham I. Fet (1924-2007). In memory of the 90th anniversary.
Topics:

Terms of use | Copyright © 2018 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters