Printer Friendly
The Free Library
23,421,980 articles and books


Wilhelm Dilthey on the objectivity of knowledge in human sciences.

1. Introduction

As a philosopher of science, Wilhelm Dilthey Wilhelm Dilthey (IPA: [ˈdɪltaɪ]; November 19, 1833 – October 1, 1911) was a German historian, psychologist, sociologist, student of hermeneutics, and philosopher.  (1833-1911) focused on human sciences or Geisteswissenschaften, a term that had gained currency in German culture. These sciences underwent a so-called crisis of foundations (Grundlagenkrise) (Lessing 1984:132-136) during Dilthey's formative formative /for·ma·tive/ (for´mah-tiv) concerned in the origination and development of an organism, part, or tissue.  years in the second half of the nineteenth century. In Germany, human sciences had evolved into sciences mainly within the framework of the concept of scientificalness (Wissenschaftlichkeit) of German Idealism German idealism was a philosophical movement in Germany in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. It developed out of the work of Immanuel Kant in the 1780s and 1790s, and was closely linked both with romanticism and the revolutionary politics of the Enlightenment. . However, during the first half of the nineteenth century the human sciences had developed into empirical research Noun 1. empirical research - an empirical search for knowledge
inquiry, research, enquiry - a search for knowledge; "their pottery deserves more research than it has received"
 sciences, which made it impossible for them to understand their own nature by means of the concept of scientificalness that had formed the basis for their development into academic disciplines (Schnadelbach 1991:108-117). On the other hand, a sound methodological research apparatus had been elaborated over the years within the various human science disciplines, to which they could resort in their ambitions to offer genuinely scientific knowledge of areas that until then had been studied basically from the metaphysical met·a·phys·i·cal  
adj.
1. Of or relating to metaphysics.

2. Based on speculative or abstract reasoning.

3. Highly abstract or theoretical; abstruse.

4.
a. Immaterial; incorporeal.
 point of view of German Idealism. In these circumstances, Dilthey saw a new role for philosophy, the status of which as an academic discipline had become somewhat unstable in the post-metaphysical era. This role consisted in providing the existing research methodology of contemporary human sciences with the philosophical-epistemological foundation that it still lacked.

As a negative consequence of the above-mentioned lack, he points out the groundlessness ground·less  
adj.
Having no ground or foundation; unsubstantiated: groundless optimism. See Synonyms at baseless.



ground
 of the validity pretensions of knowledge as the human sciences view it, which undermines their inherent aspiration aspiration /as·pi·ra·tion/ (as?pi-ra´shun)
1. the drawing of a foreign substance, such as the gastric contents, into the respiratory tract during inhalation.

2.
 to provide rules for the optimal management of social life. It is especially characteristic of Dilthey's reasoning that the solution of these two tasks coincides, as he sees it: the very substantiation of the objectivity of the research results of human sciences would guarantee the ability of these sciences to react back on life and society (Dilthey 2002:159).

Thus we could say that Dilthey's deliberations of the objectivity of scientific knowledge are motivated by two aspirations aspirations nplaspiraciones fpl (= ambition); ambición f

aspirations npl (= hopes, ambition) → aspirations fpl 
. On the one hand, to form an adequate self-understanding for the human sciences of themselves as legitimate members of the scientific community. On the other hand, to motivate the pretensions of human sciences to become the instrument of consciously shaping the social life.

In its endeavours to elaborate the epistemology epistemology (ĭpĭs'təmŏl`əjē) [Gr.,=knowledge or science], the branch of philosophy that is directed toward theories of the sources, nature, and limits of knowledge. Since the 17th cent.  of scientific knowledge, German philosophy relied on the national tradition, especially on the philosophical legacy of Immanuel Kant. "Back to Kant" became the catchword for a number of diverse philosophical quests in the second half of the nineteenth century in Germany. Dilthey, too, was influenced by this movement, as the very ambitious name that he gave to his epistemological e·pis·te·mol·o·gy  
n.
The branch of philosophy that studies the nature of knowledge, its presuppositions and foundations, and its extent and validity.



[Greek epist
 aspirations testifies. Thus he set out to create "the critique of historical reason", i.e. to complete in the philosophy of human sciences something analogous to what he thought Kant had achieved within the framework of his critique of reason in elaborating the epistemological foundations of natural sciences.

In accordance with the general Kantian views, Dilthey proceeds in his philosophy from the analysis of consciousness, attributing a major role to the synthetic activeness of human spirit in the formation of human world view, just like Kant had done before him. Likewise, he adopts in general lines Kant's idea of the objectivity of scientific knowledge, according to according to
prep.
1. As stated or indicated by; on the authority of: according to historians.

2. In keeping with: according to instructions.

3.
 which the latter consists in the strictly general and inevitable validity of knowledge about experienced reality. In Dilthey's opinion, Kant had managed to present convincingly the conditions of the possibility of the objectivity of cognition cognition

Act or process of knowing. Cognition includes every mental process that may be described as an experience of knowing (including perceiving, recognizing, conceiving, and reasoning), as distinguished from an experience of feeling or of willing.
 in natural sciences. At the same time he was positive that it was not possible to treat cognition in human sciences in an adequate manner by proceeding from the conditions that Kant had delineated de·lin·e·ate  
tr.v. de·lin·e·at·ed, de·lin·e·at·ing, de·lin·e·ates
1. To draw or trace the outline of; sketch out.

2. To represent pictorially; depict.

3.
 in the area of natural sciences. This, in its turn, induces Dilthey to modify Kant's transcendentalism transcendentalism, American literary and philosophical movement
transcendentalism (trăn'sĕndĕn`təlĭzəm) [Lat.
 on a large scale. In the course of this process, the concept of objectivity also undergoes a certain change. Kant regarded the general and inevitable relations between natural phenomena as objects of objective knowledge. From the point of view of human sciences, which emerged after Kant's days, unique phenomena, too, were considered to be legitimate objects of research. In fact, Dilthey regarded unique cultural phenomena as the most significant field of research of this branch of science. Thus we could conclude that objective knowledge in human sciences should also contain the universally valid knowledge of unique objects.

By and large, Dilthey's treatment of objectivity seems to have two focuses. In his earlier creative period, the grounding of the objectivity of human sciences consists in the demonstration of the fact that the ambition of these sciences to grasp reality is justified. In his later phase, however, he focuses on substantiating sub·stan·ti·ate  
tr.v. sub·stan·ti·at·ed, sub·stan·ti·at·ing, sub·stan·ti·ates
1. To support with proof or evidence; verify: substantiate an accusation. See Synonyms at confirm.
 the universal validity of cognitive achievements in the domain of human sciences. I shall take a closer look at the respective approaches in the two subsequent parts of the present article.

2. Objectivity as correspondence to reality

Dilthey's epistemological analysis proceeds from one fundamental principle. He calls this the principle of phenomenality (Satz der Phanomenalitat): "The supreme principle of philosophy is the principle of phenomenality: according to this principle everything that exists for me is subject to the condition that it is a fact of my consciousness. All outer things, too, are only given as a connection of facts or processes of the consciousness. Objects, things, only exist for, and in, consciousness" (Dilthey 1974a:90). This principle stresses the point that whenever man experiences something, on the most elementary level, it is a fact of his consciousness, although the non-philosophical mind is not aware of this. The term "facts of consciousness" emphasizes the significance of this principle in Dilthey's philosophical analysis Philosophical analysis is a general term for techniques typically used by philosophers in the analytic tradition that involve "breaking down" (i.e. analyzing) philosophical issues.  as pointing to a special domain of facts. The science, therefore, that should deal with the given domain of facts, is philosophy as the universal empirical discipline. It does rely on a specific mode of experience, but experience nevertheless, and this should guarantee philosophy a respectable status among other empirical sciences.

According to Dilthey, the principle of phenomenality is the only reliable point of departure for philosophy primarily due to the fact that if there is reason at all to state that something exists, it is only in this way and inasmuch as in·as·much as  
conj.
1. Because of the fact that; since.

2. To the extent that; insofar as.


inasmuch as
conj

1. since; because

2.
 it is a fact of consciousness. Dilthey understands philosophy, first and foremost, as "a guide for methodically me·thod·i·cal   also me·thod·ic
adj.
1. Arranged or proceeding in regular, systematic order.

2. Characterized by ordered and systematic habits or behavior. See Synonyms at orderly.
 grasping grasping

a similar equine neurosis to windsucking; the horse grasps a fixed object with its teeth, but does not swallow air.
 reality, the real world in pure experience, and for analyzing it within the limits prescribed pre·scribe  
v. pre·scribed, pre·scrib·ing, pre·scribes

v.tr.
1. To set down as a rule or guide; enjoin. See Synonyms at dictate.

2. To order the use of (a medicine or other treatment).
 by the critique of knowledge" (Dilthey 1989:173). Thus the principle of phenomenality, according to Dilthey's intention, should serve as a point of departure for moving towards the solution of the central problem of his epistemology--to ground the pretension Pretension
See also Hypocrisy.

Prey (See QUARRY.)

Pride (See BOASTFULNESS, EGOTISM, VANITY.)

Absolon

vain, officious parish clerk. [Br. Lit.
 of scientific knowledge, especially that of the human science knowledge, to capture reality.

The concept condensed con·dense  
v. con·densed, con·dens·ing, con·dens·es

v.tr.
1. To reduce the volume or compass of.

2. To make more concise; abridge or shorten.

3. Physics
a.
 in the principle of phenomenality has also its critical side--Dilthey applies it to his critique of metaphysics metaphysics (mĕtəfĭz`ĭks), branch of philosophy concerned with the ultimate nature of existence. It perpetuates the Metaphysics of Aristotle, a collection of treatises placed after the Physics [Gr. . The very essence of metaphysics, he argues, lies in the attempts to find behind the facts of consciousness something that would allow one to deduce de·duce  
tr.v. de·duced, de·duc·ing, de·duc·es
1. To reach (a conclusion) by reasoning.

2. To infer from a general principle; reason deductively:
 the facts of consciousness, and this way to explain them by means of purely intellectual apprehension. The principle of phenomenality, therefore, indicates the limit of reasonable cognitive pretension which, as Dilthey saw it, had been uncritically crossed by traditional metaphysics. Dilthey also views Kant's concept of Ding an sich as a metaphysical relic, by which the founder of transcendental philosophy betrayed his own critical method.

Dilthey calls the specific mode of experience, by which we become aware of what exists for us as a fact of consciousness, Innewerden, or reflexive (theory) reflexive - A relation R is reflexive if, for all x, x R x.

Equivalence relations, pre-orders, partial orders and total orders are all reflexive.
 awareness. By this term he denotes the primordial primordial /pri·mor·di·al/ (pri-mor´de-al) primitive.

pri·mor·di·al
adj.
1. Being or happening first in sequence of time; primary; original.

2.
 unity of consciousness. Dilthey argues that Innewerden as the most simple modality modality /mo·dal·i·ty/ (mo-dal´i-te)
1. a method of application of, or the employment of, any therapeutic agent, especially a physical agent.

2.
 of consciousness precedes the division of subject and object, of form and content, and of act and content, by means of which the structure of consciousness was commonly described. This is a groundbreaking subject-object-identity. For this reason, Dilthey believes that the reflexive awareness of facts of consciousness on the given level is characterized by the highest degree of immediacy im·me·di·a·cy  
n. pl. im·me·di·a·cies
1. The condition or quality of being immediate.

2. Lack of an intervening or mediating agency; directness: the immediacy of live television coverage.
 and certainty.

When viewed from the genealogical ge·ne·al·o·gy  
n. pl. ge·ne·al·o·gies
1. A record or table of the descent of a person, family, or group from an ancestor or ancestors; a family tree.

2. Direct descent from an ancestor; lineage or pedigree.
 aspect, Dilthey treats Innewerden as "the most simple form in which psychic life can appear" (Dilthey 1989:254). The unity of consciousness that becomes aware in Innewerden remains in the sphere of consciousness that precedes the explicit self-consciousness. Accordingly, there is no self-consciousness as yet in Innewerden, it being primary in genealogical terms, that would clearly differentiate itself from the consciousness of outer reality. Nevertheless, it could still be called "pre-intentional" (Makkreel 1992), inasmuch In`as`much´

adv. 1. In like degree; in like manner; seeing that; considering that; since; - followed by as. See In as much as, under In,

prep.
 Innewerden is related to the world even when the world has not been conceived as object as yet. The evolution of consciousness consists in the formation of a distinct self-consciousness, and of the consciousness of the world that is related to it.

Therefore, consciousness should be regarded as the nexus of life. The concept of "life", central to Dilthey's theorizing, denotes the continuous self-domination, consisting of actions and reactions, between the "self" and the natural and social world, and the resultant experience. The term "lived experience" (Erlebnis) thus designates the particular experienced conflict between action and reaction at a given moment of time.

The lived experience is the smallest indivisible INDIVISIBLE. That which cannot be separated.
     2. It is important to ascertain when a consideration or a contract, is or is not indivisible. When a consideration is entire and indivisible, and it is against law, the contract is void in toto. 11 Verm. 592; 2 W.
 meaningful phenomenon of life. It represents an internally divided totality TOTALITY. The whole sum or quantity.
     2. In making a tender, it is requisite that the totality of the sum due should be offered, together with the interest and costs. Vide Tender.
, the structure of which always contains the connection of cognitive, emotional and volitional vo·li·tion  
n.
1. The act or an instance of making a conscious choice or decision.

2. A conscious choice or decision.

3. The power or faculty of choosing; the will.
 processes. Dilthey's main critique of the earlier philosophy of consciousness, including that of Kant, is that it reduces the human experience exclusively to its cognitive aspect. This, he argues, does not allow us to explicate the human experience of the outer world adequately. Our selfhood self·hood  
n.
1. The state of having a distinct identity; individuality.

2. The fully developed self; an achieved personality.

3.
 is at the same time always a lived experience of the world in which we live, so that the lived experience of the world is simultaneously the experience of our world. Yet there is still no subject-object or inner world-outer world dichotomy di·chot·o·my  
n. pl. di·chot·o·mies
1. Division into two usually contradictory parts or opinions: "the dichotomy of the one and the many" Louis Auchincloss.
 in this lived experience. In the light of the aforesaid Before, already said, referred to, or recited.

This term is used frequently in deeds, leases, and contracts of sale of real property to refer to the property without describing it in detail each time it is mentioned; for example,"the aforesaid premises.
, we can conclude that the term "lived experience" for Dilthey does not signify sig·ni·fy  
v. sig·ni·fied, sig·ni·fy·ing, sig·ni·fies

v.tr.
1. To denote; mean.

2. To make known, as with a sign or word: signify one's intent.
 man's inner emotional state but his openness to the reality of life and his immediate awareness of this. From the epistemological perspective, then, it is significant at this point that Dilthey considers this lived experience as immediately present and unquestionably un·ques·tion·a·ble  
adj.
Beyond question or doubt. See Synonyms at authentic.



un·question·a·bil
 given to man, and therefore as certain.

From this concept of presupposed certainty, Dilthey hopes to deduce the foundation for the certainty of contentions elaborated in the research works of special sciences. In this context, then, philosophy as the science of the facts of consciousness should, for this reason, become a universal science of foundation in relation to special sciences. He sees it as his primary task to analyse the relations of the facts of consciousness, and to present as integral a description of these as possible. The arguments made in various natural and human scientific disciplines should be ultimately verified by tracing them back to this connection of facts of consciousness. Johannes Romelt calls that kind of verification plan the two-layered model of knowledge. According to Dilthey, any knowledge can stem from experience only. But experience itself is divided into two layers. The fundamental layer of experience consists of facts of consciousness captured in Innewerden and lived experience immediately, and therefore unmistakably un·mis·tak·a·ble  
adj.
Impossible to mistake or misinterpret; obvious: unmistakable signs of illness.



un
. The derived layer of experience is formed by the observation results of empirical special sciences, which might be erroneous erroneous adj. 1) in error, wrong. 2) not according to established law, particularly in a legal decision or court ruling.  and, being in principle open to correction, require verification on the fundamental level of experience (Romelt 1999:185-186).

Such substantiation of scientific knowledge faces major difficulties. The latter have been thoroughly analysed in various scholarly writings Scholarly writing is the genre of writing used in colleges and universities by students and professors to report and share knowledge. Characteristics
It consists of certain conventions that can vary between disciplines, but always involves:
 (e.g. Ineichen 1975, 1991, Romelt 1999). The scope of the present article, however, does not allow us to take a closer look at them. It should be mentioned in this connection, though, that Dilthey himself was aware of a major drawback DRAWBACK, com. law. An allowance made by the government to merchants on the reexportation of certain imported goods liable to duties, which, in some cases, consists of the whole; in others, of a part of the duties which had been paid upon the importation.  in the treatment of the problem. Namely, he was forced to admit that the lived experience of the world that had a central role to play in his epistemology, was inevitably related to the situation and perspective of a definite person. This, however, endangers the attainment of the other aspect of objectivity--universal validity--by such strategy of substantiation.

3. Objectivity as universal validity

The topic of the universal validity of cognition in human sciences is therefore becoming ever more prominent in the late period of his work. On the one hand, he does emphasize the circumstance that objective knowledge in human sciences has a different sense than it has in natural sciences: "The objectivity of knowledge that is sought here has a different sense; the methods for approaching the ideal of objectivity of knowledge here display essential differences from those by which we approach the conceptual cognition of nature" (Dilthey 2002a:92). On the other hand, the very ability of human sciences to exert influence on the management of social life depends, in his opinion, on the universal validity of the results of human sciences. He regards such ability as essentially characteristic of these sciences (De Mul 2004:259-260).

Under the influence of these considerations, his treatment of human sciences undergoes a certain change in the form of a shift in some significant accents in the late period of his work. Besides the concepts of life and lived experience that until then had been at the very core of his treatment, the emphasis on the role of understanding in the constitution of the cognitive relation, characteristic of human sciences, becomes more prominent. In his work that appeared in 1910, "The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences", Dilthey characterizes these sciences as follows: "A discipline belongs to the human sciences only if its object is accessible to us through the attitude that is founded upon the nexus of life, expression, and understanding" (Dilthey 2002b:109). Dilthey formulated the definition of understanding, which proved to be groundbreaking throughout the late period of his work, in his article that was published in 1900, "The Rise of Hermeneutics hermeneutics, the theory and practice of interpretation. During the Reformation hermeneutics came into being as a special discipline concerned with biblical criticism. ": "Thus we call understanding a process, in which we perceive this psychic course of life on the basis of the sensuously sen·su·ous  
adj.
1. Of, relating to, or derived from the senses.

2. Appealing to or gratifying the senses.

3.
a. Readily affected through the senses.

b.
 given signs that are the expression of it" (Dilthey 1974b:318). The cited definition stresses the fact that the mediation of perception by means of signs given in outer experience is essential to understanding. Alongside the term "sensuously given signs", Dilthey uses in his later texts synonymous expressions like sensuously perceived "expressions of life" (Lebensausserungen), and "expressions" (Ausdrucke).

He concedes in the abovementioned a·bove·men·tioned  
adj.
Mentioned previously.

n.
The one or ones mentioned previously.
 article that the lived experience alone as a basis of cognition is not sufficient enough to guarantee the objectivity of knowledge. Even if we assume that the lived experience renders the experience of reality that proceeds from it immediate certainty, the latter would still involve only the particular person alone. How would one advance from that kind of certainty to the universally valid cognition of experience? It is in this connection that Dilthey emphasizes the fact that objective cognition must be based on something external, continuously fixed, and thus intersubjectively accessible to examination. According to his new apprehension, this is the function of the expressions mediated me·di·ate  
v. me·di·at·ed, me·di·at·ing, me·di·ates

v.tr.
1. To resolve or settle (differences) by working with all the conflicting parties:
 by the external experience of human action. This is what cognition in human sciences is all about--the methodical-critical understanding or interpretation.

In his work mentioned above, "The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences", Dilthey adds an important specification to his notion of understanding. Having defined understanding as a process in which we apprehend this psychic course of life on the basis of the sensuously given expressions of life, he stresses the autonomy of the domain of spiritual objects in relation to the psychic processes more explicitly than in his earlier texts: "Here it is a common error to resort to the psychic course of life--psychology--to account for our knowledge of this inner aspect." (Dilthey 2002b:106). The understanding of that spirit is not psychological cognition. It is a regression to a spiritual formation that has its own structure and lawfulness law·ful  
adj.
1. Being within the law; allowed by law: lawful methods of dissent.

2. Established, sanctioned, or recognized by the law: the lawful heir.
. The object of understanding is not so much the inner processes of the author but the nexus, which, having been created by the author, then becomes independent (Dilthey 2002b:107). He now describes the understanding of the spiritual formation in human sciences in terms of understanding the meanings of expressions of life. Although these meanings are formed through the psychic life of individuals, they are not identical to those. Whereas the psychic life of the one that creates the meanings is not (at least in its entirety) intersubjectively reproducible, and cannot therefore be the object of universally valid knowledge, in the case of meanings such cognition is possible.

Dilthey delineates the culture-creating activeness of mankind in the same work as the all-encompassing "objectification ob·jec·ti·fy  
tr.v. ob·jec·ti·fied, ob·jec·ti·fy·ing, ob·jec·ti·fies
1. To present or regard as an object: "Because we have objectified animals, we are able to treat them impersonally" 
" or "objectification of life" (Dilthey 2002b: 168). By objectification he means, on the one hand, the externalization The ability to easily connect to and transfer information between business partners. Increasingly, information systems are designed to make their data available to outside partners and customers. This type of collaboration is expected to be a vital part of IT in the 21st century. See EDI.  of human productivity, its becoming intersubjectively accessible, but on the other hand, its representation in the human "sphere of commonality com·mon·al·i·ty  
n. pl. com·mon·al·i·ties
1.
a. The possession, along with another or others, of a certain attribute or set of attributes: a political movement's commonality of purpose.
" and "universality". He denotes the latter by a term he has borrowed from Hegel, "objective spirit". The common mentality of the society is expressed and accumulated in the objectifications of life. Wishing also to distance himself from Hegel as a metaphysician met·a·phy·si·cian  
n.
One who specializes or is skilled in metaphysics.
, Dilthey stresses the point that his concept of life is broader than his predecessor's concept of spirit, encompassing besides the universal and the rational the singular and the irrational as well.

Life and spirit manifest themselves both in the material products of human activity and in the institutional forms of society, its culture systems and external organization. All these together form "this great outer reality of human spirit" (Dilthey 2002b:168) that surrounds us everywhere. The objectifications of life open up the access to life's historical dimension through understanding, since the heritage of the earlier eras of human commonality is ever present in the form of objectifications. This heritage, had it remained just a phenomenon of individual spiritual life, would have been lost for the next generations. Thus the individual lives in the historically formed world and actualizes constantly the historical experience of the given human society, while partaking of the fixed spirit through the objectifications of life. Hence the historically universal spirituality, the "objective spirit", manifests itself in the objectifications of life. This spirit, as Dilthey now emphasizes, cannot be psychologically perceived. It is by this term that he specifies further the concept of human sciences--"everything in which human spirit has objectified itself falls within the scope of the human sciences" (Dilthey 2002b:170).

Dilthey characterizes the inner structure of the objective spirit as a complex of productive nexuses (Wirkungszusammenhange). The notion of productive nexuses refers to the connection of certain concepts, value assessments and aims, that serves as a basis for creating specific good. Such connections are characterized by historical development, during which process they acquire an ever more differentiated inner structure on the one hand, while on the other hand they are also subject to change, forming new values and altering, accordingly, the aims to be reached. The agents of the productive nexuses are, first and foremost, individuals, but also most diverse human associations that have been formed on the basis of common values for the purpose of creating good.

It is in the sphere of influence of the productive nexuses that the personality of man is formed. Men are, in fact, the "points of intersection" of productive nexuses (Dilthey 2002b:176). The objective spirit forms human subjectivity through them. This holds true for man as the subject of cognition as well. Following Kant's views, Dilthey regards the basic structures of the synthesizing action of the cognizing subject as the condition of the possibility of scientific knowledge. At the same time, he rejects Kant's theory of the timeless timeless,
adj infinite, enduring, endless.
 transcendental subject. He has replaced it with the concept of the empirical-historical subject, the basic structures of the action of which are socio-culturally moulded and subject to historical change. Dilthey calls such basic structures of the subject's synthesizing activeness the categories of life. He points out that in contrast to Kant's formal categories, which in Dilthey's view are deduced from the kind of thinking that is separate from the original nexus of life, the life categories evolve along the basic lines of the human-historical-social life, and for this reason form the constituents of the apprehension process of such life. Because of the significance of these for the comprehension of life objectification in human sciences, he singles out such categories as meaning and sense, part and whole, temporality tem·po·ral·i·ty  
n. pl. tem·po·ral·i·ties
1. The condition of being temporal or bounded in time.

2. temporalities Temporal possessions, especially of the Church or clergy.

Noun 1.
, connection, structure, value, aim, development, and also essence.

At the same time, Dilthey seems to be of the opinion that the possibility of objectivity towards which the cognition of human science strives for is, above all, associated with the qualities of the object that is being interpreted, rather than with the structure of the subject of cognition. As mentioned before, it must be continuously and accessibly fixed for the external experience, which makes it possible to subject it to long-time intersubjectively controlled examination. The various ways of fixation fixation: see psychoanalysis. , however, are not equal in this function for Dilthey. In a posthumously post·hu·mous  
adj.
1. Occurring or continuing after one's death: a posthumous award.

2. Published after the writer's death: a posthumous book.

3.
 published manuscript he divides the various expressions of life into three groups: (1) concepts, judgements and larger thought formations; (2) actions, and (3) expressions of lived experience (Dilthey 2002c:226-227). In the analysis that follows, he regards these expressions of life as important for human sciences on the basis of the extent to which they open up the integral life nexus that is ultimately the foundation of them all. Since the most complete access to the latter can be obtained through the understanding of the expressions of lived experience, Dilthey centres his analysis on the understanding that corresponds to this particular type of expressions. He attaches next to no importance to the type of understanding that corresponds to the first group of expressions, for this kind of expressions "have been detached from the lived experience in which they arose" (Dilthey 2002c:225). He pays more attention to the type of understanding that corresponds to the second group of expressions, since in these the inner essence of selfhood is at least partly expressed. However, as mentioned before, he singles out the expressions of lived experience as the most multifarious multifarious adj., adv. reference to a lawsuit in which either party or various causes of action (claims based on different legal theories) are improperly joined together in the same suit. This is more commonly called "misjoinder." (See: misjoinder)  manifestation of the nexus of life. Yet even these, he argues, can be unreliable as sources of objective understanding, for such expressions could also be feigned feigned  
adj.
1. Not real; pretended: a feigned modesty.

2. Made-up; fictitious.

Adj. 1.
, and therefore misleading. A possibility like that is in Dilthey's opinion excluded, though, in the case of one category

of expressions of lived experience--namely, that of artistic, religious or philosophical creativity. Among these, he in particular stresses the role of written expressions of lived experience as the basis of objective knowledge: "Since it is only in language that the life of mind and spirit finds its complete and exhaustive expression--one that makes objective comprehension possible--exegesis culminates in the interpretation of the written records of human existence. This art is the basis of philology phi·lol·o·gy  
n.
1. Literary study or classical scholarship.

2. See historical linguistics.



[Middle English philologie, from Latin philologia, love of learning
. The science of this art is hermeneutics" (Dilthey 2002c:237-238).

Since Dilthey attributes to language the privileged status of understanding life expression, in his view, then, the comprehension of language is the "archetypal ar·che·type  
n.
1. An original model or type after which other similar things are patterned; a prototype: "'Frankenstein' . . . 'Dracula' . . . 'Dr. Jekyll and Mr. Hyde' . . .
" form of any understanding. He specifies the process of comprehending a linguistic expression as "determining the indeterminate That which is uncertain or not particularly designated.


INDETERMINATE. That which is uncertain or not particularly designated; as, if I sell you one hundred bushels of wheat, without stating what wheat. 1 Bouv. Inst. n. 950.
". Single isolated words have several "determinate-indeterminate" meanings (Bedeutungen) (Dilthey 2002c:241). They acquire a definite meaning only in the relations within the sentence. The combination of single word meanings in a definite sentence (logic) definite sentence - A collection of definite clauses.  yields the sense of the latter. Thus the understanding of a language is primarily the comprehension of meanings and sense. Meaning and sense are the fundamental categories of Dilthey's conception of understanding and interpretation.

Since word meanings relate to the sense of the sentence as parts to the whole, the understanding is characterized from the beginning as the connection of two basic operations: the whole should be understood through its component parts and the component parts through the whole. Such circular relation occurs in the very understanding of the sentence, but it becomes even more prominent in the interpretation of integral written texts. What we have here is the circular interdependence in·ter·de·pen·dent  
adj.
Mutually dependent: "Today, the mission of one institution can be accomplished only by recognizing that it lives in an interdependent world with conflicts and overlapping interests" 
, repeatedly described in the history of hermeneutics, which is characteristic of understanding the text. Part and whole form the other groundbreaking pair of categories in Dilthey's hermeneutical philosophy.

Next Dilthey proceeds from the prerequisite that the categories mentioned in connection with understanding language are applicable to the interpretation of life objectification in general. "Just as words have a meaning by which they designate something, and sentences have a sense that we construe construe v. to determine the meaning of the words of a written document, statute or legal decision, based upon rules of legal interpretation as well as normal meanings. , so we can construe the connectedness of life from the determinate-indeterminate meaning of its parts. Meaning is the special relation that parts have to the whole within life. We recognize this meaning, as we do that of the words in a sentence, by virtue of memories and future possibilities. The essence of meaning relations lies in the shaping of a life-course over time on the basis of life-structure as conditioned by a milieu mi·lieu
n. pl. mi·lieus or mi·lieux
1. The totality of one's surroundings; an environment.

2. The social setting of a mental patient.



milieu

[Fr.] surroundings, environment.
" (Dilthey 2002c:253-254). A single expression of life has meaning when it stands as a sign in the referential relation to something that differs from it. This is why we cannot, within the framework of the given system of concepts, speak about the meaning of life in general--in Dilthey's philosophy, life is the final irreducible irreducible /ir·re·duc·i·ble/ (ir?i-doo´si-b'l) not susceptible to reduction, as a fracture, hernia, or chemical substance.

ir·re·duc·i·ble
adj.
1.
 reality that cannot, for this reason, refer to anything different from itself. The apprehension of life as a whole lies in understanding its sense, which is formed of the encompassing relationship of its meaningful component parts. Since life, according to Dilthey, is given to man in his lived experiences, the structural connection of lived experiences is constituted by sense. Thus, meaning is the fundamental category of understanding lived experience. Lived experience attains unity by its meaning.

Human sciences, as Dilthey sees it, should on the one hand aspire as·pire  
intr.v. as·pired, as·pir·ing, as·pires
1. To have a great ambition or ultimate goal; desire strongly: aspired to stardom.

2.
 towards the analysis of the structures of meaning of the "objective spirit" entailed in the social-historical world. On the other hand, though, they should aim at connecting the single expressions of lived experiences to particular larger structures of meanings. Thus the process of understanding in human sciences is characterized by two-way movement: it tries to integrate the meaningful separate aspects into the unity of sense and, at the same time, to reconstruct re·con·struct  
tr.v. re·con·struct·ed, re·con·struct·ing, re·con·structs
1. To construct again; rebuild.

2.
 the unity of sense by taking into account the meanings of its constituent parts. In order to attain the general validity of understanding, both these directions of apprehension function in the reciprocally complementary and corrective manner. The cognition of social-historical individualities lies, on the one hand, in the treatment of the latter as products of structures of meanings and of productive nexuses, and, on the other hand, as the agents of further development of these productive nexuses themselves.

The total nexus of all these meaningful constituent areas is the nexus of life, which is accessible through the understanding of single expressions of lived experience. Life in its course is in Dilthey's view a succession of lived experiences, the meanings of which are subject to change until the end of life. But in contrast to individual lives lived in the past, the historical life has never ended, and for this reason one can assume that the expressions of lived experience fixed in objectification will keep joining to ever new wholes as totalities of sense and constellations Constellations
Constellation English name Position
R.A.
(hours)
DEC.
(degrees)

Andromeda Andromeda (Chained Lady) 1 +43
Antlia Air Pump 10 −33
Apus Bird of Paradise 16 −75
Aquarius1
 of meaning. This circumstance, however, questions the very aspiration of human sciences to attain the universal validity of the knowledge of the meanings and sense of life objectification.

Dilthey seems to have found a solution to this problem in the treatment of larger productive nexuses centred in themselves as wholes. He considers nations and historical periods as examples of such productive nexuses. In Dilthey's view, the latter are characterized by a more intense inner intercourse in comparison with other productive nexuses, and also by a stronger reluctance towards any possible influences from the outside. If they do receive influences from the outside world, these will be assimilated into the structures of meaning of the era or nation itself. At the centre of such structure, Dilthey argues, is the nexus of the dominant world view, value assessments and set goals. In relation to this nexus as the whole, all other life objectifications within the horizon of the given productive nexus acquire significance as parts of this whole. The research of human sciences must place itself into this kind of wholes and describe them immanently. The completeness and self-centeredness of such wholes, the connections between the involved productive nexuses and the shared mentality should, according to Dilthey's expectations, enable the methodically-critically founded descriptions to attain universal validity (Dilthey 2002b:159-160, 175-187).

4. Objectivity and the social-practical role of human sciences

It is easy to notice the weak points of such substantiation of objectivity. The limited scope of the present article does not allow us to present a more detailed analysis of these at this point. I would, instead, concentrate on the issue of why the founding of the objectivity of cognition in human sciences as the attainability of the universal validity of knowledge was important for Dilthey, to begin with. As he saw it, the ability of the given type of knowledge to exert optimizing counter influence on social life depended on the objectivity of this knowledge. This very ability to exert such influence, however, was in Dilthey's view essential to human sciences as the forms of the theoretical and practical self-reflection of society. However, it now appears that the attainability of the objectivity of knowledge depends on whether the phenomenon under inspection is separated from the life situation of the investigator in terms of a sufficient historical and cultural distance. Purportedly, objectivity can be achieved primarily by adapting oneself to such productive nexuses, but it is fairly problematic in relation to the perception of the productive nexus in which one lives.

Thus it appears that Dilthey's theorizing on the objectivity of human sciences does not yield the desired results. The human-scientific grounding of objectivity in the sense of the justification of the perception of reality, towards which these sciences aspire, questioned the very objectivity of these in the sense of the universal validity of knowledge. The reasoning that was to justify the aspirations of human sciences towards universally valid knowledge undermined the very ability of these sciences to affect contemporary society.

This might well be the reason why Dilthey has changed his views on the social-practical role of human sciences in his later works, although he has not said so in plain words Plain Words is a style guide for British English written in 1948 by Sir Ernest Gowers, and expanded and reissued in 1954 as The Complete Plain Words (ISBN 0-14-051199-7). . He now talks about the historical consciousness created by these as the liberation of man. "The historical consciousness of the finitude fin·i·tude  
n.
The quality or condition of being finite.

Noun 1. finitude - the quality of being finite
boundedness, finiteness
 of every historical phenomenon and of every human or social state, and of the relativity of every kind of faith, is the final step toward the liberation of human beings" (Dilthey 2002c:310). But the kind of liberty he speaks about is no longer associated with social change but with the widening of the scope of man's horizon of lived experience through the interpretation of historical and artistic objectifications. By means of such cognition in human sciences, "human beings who are determined from within can experience many other kinds of existence through the imagination. Confined con·fine  
v. con·fined, con·fin·ing, con·fines

v.tr.
1. To keep within bounds; restrict: Please confine your remarks to the issues at hand. See Synonyms at limit.
 by circumstances, they can nevertheless glimpse exotic beauties of the world and regions of life beyond their reach. Put generally: Human beings bound and limited by the reality of life are liberated lib·er·ate  
tr.v. lib·er·at·ed, lib·er·at·ing, lib·er·ates
1. To set free, as from oppression, confinement, or foreign control.

2. Chemistry To release (a gas, for example) from combination.
 not only by art--as has often been claimed--but also by the understanding of the historical" (Dilthey 2002c:237).

Address:

Andrus Tool

Department of Philosophy

University of Tartu At different times during its history the University of Tartu was known as Academia Gustaviana, University of Dorpat, '' Universität (zu) Dorpat, University of Yuryev, and Tartu State University (Tartu Riiklik Ülikool)''.  

Lossi 3

50090 Tartu

E-mail: atool@hot.ee

Phone: +372 738 8224

References

De Mul, Jos (2004) The Tragedy of Finitude. Dilthey's Hermeneutics of Life. New Haven New Haven, city (1990 pop. 130,474), New Haven co., S Conn., a port of entry where the Quinnipiac and other small rivers enter Long Island Sound; inc. 1784. Firearms and ammunition, clocks and watches, tools, rubber and paper products, and textiles are among the many  & London: Yale University Yale University, at New Haven, Conn.; coeducational. Chartered as a collegiate school for men in 1701 largely as a result of the efforts of James Pierpont, it opened at Killingworth (now Clinton) in 1702, moved (1707) to Saybrook (now Old Saybrook), and in 1716 was  Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm Dilthey, Wilhelm (vĭl`hĕlm dĭl`tī), 1833–1911, German philosopher. He taught at the universities of Basel, Kiel, Breslau, and Berlin.  (1989) Selected works. Volume I: Introduction to the human sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Princeton University, at Princeton, N.J.; coeducational; chartered 1746, opened 1747, rechartered 1748, called the College of New Jersey until 1896. Schools and Research Facilities
 Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm (2002a) "The Delimitation of the Human Sciences". In Selected Works. Vol. 3, pp. 91-97. Wilhelm Dilthey, ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm (2002b) "The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences". In Selected Works. Vol. 3, pp. 101-209. Wilhelm Dilthey, ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm (2002c) "Plan for the Continuation of the Formation of the Historical World in Human Sciences". In Selected Works. Vol. 3, pp. 213-311. Wilhelm Dilthey, ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm (1974a) "Beitrage zur Losung der Frage vom Ursprung unseres Glaubens an Realitat der Aussenwelt und seinem Recht". In Gesammelte Schriften. Bd. 5, 6. Aufl. Wilhelm Dilthey, ed. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck&Ruprecht, S. 90-138.

Dilthey, Wilhelm (1974b) "Die Entstehung der Hermeneutik" In Gesammelte Schriften. Bd. 5, 6. Aufl. Wilhelm Dilthey, ed. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck&Ruprecht, S. 317-338.

Ineichen, Hans (1975) Erkenntnistheorie und geschichtlich-gesellschaftliche Welt. Diltheys Logik der Geisteswissenschaften. Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.

Ineichen, Hans (1991) Philosophische Hermeneutik. Freiburg/Munchen: Karl Alber Verlag.

Lessing, Hans-Ulrich (1984) Die Idee einer Kritik der historischen Vernunft. Wilhelm Diltheys erkenntnistheoretisch-logisch-metodologische Grundlegung der Geisteswissenschaften. Freiburg/ Munchen: Karl Alber Verlag.

Makkreel, Rudolf (1992) Dilthey: Philosopher of the Human Studies. Princeton

Romelt, Johannes (1999) Die Kant-Kritik Wilhelm Diltheys und das Problem der Legitimierung von Erfahrungserkenntnis. Kevelaer: Butzon und Bercker.

Schnadelbach, Herbert (1991) Philosophie in Deutschland 1831-1933. 4. Aufl. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

Andrus Tool

University of Tartu
COPYRIGHT 2007 Estonian Academy Publishers
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2007 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 Reader Opinion

Title:

Comment:



 

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Tool, Andrus
Publication:Trames
Date:Mar 1, 2007
Words:5511
Next Article:Poesie der musik: zur intermedialitat in Robert Schumanns fruhen schriften/Poetry and music: on the intermediality in the early writings of Robert...

Terms of use | Copyright © 2014 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters