Printer Friendly
The Free Library
22,728,960 articles and books

The Ethical Lacunae in Friedman's concept of the manager.



Milton Friedman Noun 1. Milton Friedman - United States economist noted as a proponent of monetarism and for his opposition to government intervention in the economy (born in 1912)
Friedman
 promotes two doctrines in Capitalism and Freedom. The first is in regard to the proper role and use of corporate profits. The second is in regard to the moral foundations required for a stable society. Unfortunately, Friedman's doctrine on profit is often applied without reference to his second doctrine on ethics (James and Rassekh 2000). In a similar way, Adam Smith's economic injunctions in The Wealth of Nations are often misunderstood because the moral underpinnings for them in The Theory of Moral Sentiments are ignored. In both cases, an understanding of economic processes is weakened (Evensky 2005; Young 1997). This article analyzes the interconnections between the instrumental role of profits and the intrinsic role of morals in Friedman's model, using for its analytical framework the moral sentiments theory of Adam Smith. The article also examines whether Friedman's profit-maximization goal adequately motivates managerial activity.

The key problem with Friedman's mandate on profits is that it gives rise to a fundamental inconsistency: On one level, Friedman utilizes a largely consequentialist ethic to explain how markets and economic actors behave, yet he simultaneously relies upon managers to uphold an internal ethic based on duty and virtue. The psychological dissonance created may produce both hypocrisy and inefficiency. A subtler version of Friedman's injunction on profits and the manager is warranted, in which virtue ethics virtue ethics

Approach to ethics that takes the notion of virtue (often conceived as excellence) as fundamental. Virtue ethics is primarily concerned with traits of character that are essential to human flourishing, not with the enumeration of duties.
 might provide a meaningful approach to motivation within the firm.

the Manager and Profits

Fiduciary Duties and Profit Maximization In economics, profit maximization is the process by which a firm determines the price and output level that returns the greatest profit. There are several approaches to this problem.  

Milton Friedman's Capitalism and Freedom contains one of the twentieth century's most quoted economic passages:
   Few trends could so thoroughly undermine the very foundations of
   our free society as the acceptance by corporate officials of a
   social responsibility other than to make as much money for their
   stockholders as possible (1962, 133).


He restates this claim in a widely reprinted article in the New York New York, state, United States
New York, Middle Atlantic state of the United States. It is bordered by Vermont, Massachusetts, Connecticut, and the Atlantic Ocean (E), New Jersey and Pennsylvania (S), Lakes Erie and Ontario and the Canadian province of
 Times Sunday Magazine (1970). There, he makes two important points. First, he argues that, "(t)he corporation is an instrument of the stockholders who own it" (1962, 135). Managers are agent-employees of the owners and charged with conducting business in accordance with the owners' wishes. This typically is interpreted to mean that managers are to make as much money as possible for the owners and to avoid other activities that reduce shareholder profits. These other activities include acts of social responsibility that funnel profits to concerns other than those approved by stockholders. To do otherwise is, in Friedman's view, a form of unfair taxation. (1)

Friedman then makes an efficiency argument based on the instrumental role that profits play in a market system. In a free and competitive market lacking externalities, profits signal the way resources ought to be used in business to best meet the preferences of consumers. In this view, managers ought not to stand in the way of the market's free functioning and should not sidetrack the business by having it attend to social problems such as homelessness, unemployment, racial disparity, poverty, and so on. These are not the bailiwick BAILIWICK. The district over which a sheriff has jurisdiction; it signifies also the same as county, the sheriff's bailiwick extending over the county.
     2.
 of business nor is there anything in the manager's training that makes him or her expert in aiding such causes. As Friedman notes: "If businessmen do have a social responsibility other than making maximum profits for stockholders, how are they to know what it is? Can self-selected private individuals decide what the social interest is?" (Ibid., 133). (2) Clearly, Friedman thinks managers cannot. Instead, they should stick to what they do best and the job they are hired to perform: maximizing wealth creation for shareholders. As we will see, however, Friedman has added an important caveat that not only limits the manager's profit seeking but also coheres with the views of an earlier free-market proponent, Adam Smith.

Caveats to Restrain Greed

Although Friedman does claim that managers ought to strive to maximize profits for shareholders, he also maintains that doing so should not be divorced from the ethical foundations on which business activity takes place. Managers, he asserts, ought to maximize profits for owners while conforming to the "basic rules of the society, both those embodied in law and those embodied in ethical custom" (1970). Unbridled profit seeking is simply unacceptable behavior if such behavior is outside the mainstream of ethical norms. Managers may neither opt out nor excuse themselves from laws and customs. Instead, they must abide by what used to be called the basic "rules of justice."

In adding this caveat, Friedman follows the lead of Adam Smith who argued forcefully against the notion that private vices are public virtues and against the belief that greed, avarice av·a·rice  
n.
Immoderate desire for wealth; cupidity.



[Middle English, from Old French, from Latin av
, and selfishness can contribute to public well-being (Calkins and Werhane 1998). In Smith's view, people engaged in competitive commerce can be virtuous because their virtues--in particular, their habits of prudence, justice, and self-command--are crucial to a well-functioning society (ibid.). Virtuous people, Smith believed, will uphold "religiously the sacred rules of justice in spite both of the greatest interests which might tempt, and the greatest injuries which might provoke [them] to violate them" (1982, 241). In short, they will exercise self-command, Smith's preeminent individual virtue.

For Smith, as for Friedman, self-interest is subsumed within an ethical framework (James and Rassekh 2000). Smith states clearly that "in the race for wealth, and honours, and preferments, he may run as hard as he can, and strain every nerve and every muscle, in order to outstrip out·strip  
tr.v. out·stripped, out·strip·ping, out·strips
1. To leave behind; outrun.

2. To exceed or surpass: "Material development outstripped human development" 
 all his competitors. But if he should justle, or throw down any of them, the indulgence of the spectators is entirely at an end. It is a violation of fair play, which they cannot admit of" (1982, 83).

This ethical framework, which includes the notion of justice as fair play, is a social and ethical, not a legal, construct. It is the platform on which character and reputation are forged: "To be anxious, or to be laying a plot either to gain or to save a single shilling, would degrade the most vulgar tradesman in the opinion of all his neighbors" (ibid., 173). For Smith, therefore, regulating oneself--exercising self-command--is of paramount importance. Not surprisingly, he regards self-command as the preeminent individual moral virtue, one from which "all the other virtues seem to derive their principal lustre lustre

In mineralogy, the appearance of a mineral surface in terms of its light-reflecting qualities. Lustre depends on a mineral's refractivity (see refraction), transparency, and structure.
" (1982, 241).

Friedman echoes the Stoic character of Smith's views when he admonishes managers to exercise self-restraint while running businesses for shareholders. He challenges them to be unselfish agents of the owners and to refrain from diverting business resources toward activities that earn economic rent for managers--such as endeavors that boost short-term profits and executive bonuses at the expense of long-term productivity and profit (Grant 1991, 911). Friedman thus espouses profit seeking but does not advocate greed. Rather, consistent with Smith, Friedman enjoins managers to stand firm against passions that would tempt them away from fulfilling the fundamental fiduciary duties associated with the principal-agent agreement and from conforming to society's legal and ethical norms.

Asymmetric Information Asymmetric Information

Information available to some people but not others.

Notes:
In other words, the asymmetric information is held by only one side, meaning someone is keeping a secret.
 and the Subtlety of Ethical Custom

While Friedman's manager is consistent with Smith's virtuous man at the abstract level of duties, is Friedman's thesis consistent at a practical level? Are there times when managers ought not to maximize profits? To answer this question, consider as an example the CEO (1) (Chief Executive Officer) The highest individual in command of an organization. Typically the president of the company, the CEO reports to the Chairman of the Board.  of a health maintenance organization (HMO HMO health maintenance organization.

HMO
n.
A corporation that is financed by insurance premiums and has member physicians and professional staff who provide curative and preventive medicine within certain financial,
). This company receives the bulk of its receipts from a third party, such as an insurance company, so that consumers and payments are separated by a semitransparent penumbra penumbra (pĭnŭm`brə): see eclipse; sunspots. . Suppose a patient visits one of these HMO doctors complaining of a backache back·ache
n.
Discomfort or a pain in the region of the back or spine.
. The doctor in this situation has many treatment options, each entailing a different level of treatment and potential profit for the HMO. What should the doctor do?

According to according to
prep.
1. As stated or indicated by; on the authority of: according to historians.

2. In keeping with: according to instructions.

3.
 Friedman's injunction, the CEO's imperative is to advance the wishes of the company's shareholders. If profit maximization is the goal, the CEO has a moral obligation to make as much profit as possible so long as no fraud is committed. Accordingly, the CEO should command that doctors prescribe the procedures, tests, and surgeries that will generate the most profit for the HMO. Because backache symptoms indicate a number of possible causes, some of which could be serious, the doctor could select the priciest treatment options while still not violating the law or ethical customs. Doctors who overtest can argue that they are being risk-averse to provide better care or to avoid lawsuits. The patient would be inclined to go along with the doctor's treatment regimen because she lacks the doctor's sophisticated knowledge. In doing so, however, she and her insurance company will pay an inflated price for treatment of her backache. Even so, no laws are broken, and the doctor conforms to society's expectation that doctors alleviate patient suffering.

Exploring the situation further, however, it becomes apparent that the CEO's promotion of profit maximization is not wholly appropriate. For one, the CEO is taking advantage of the patient's ignorance and likely violates the fiduciary trust A fiduciary trust is a fiduciary [1] relationship in which a trustee holds the title to assets for the beneficiary. The trust's creator is called the grantor. References

1.
 grounding the doctor-patient relationship. The doctor is able to prescribe the most expensive course of treatment precisely because of information and financial asymmetry and because the patient trusts that the doctor has her best interests in mind. Because it is often difficult for buyers to obtain competing information in some health-care situations, and the consequences for failing to buy may be life-or-death, this transaction can be seen as coercive (Sandel 1998). Had the patient the same information and experience as the doctor, and were the patient paying directly for the treatment, she would not be as inclined to accept the doctor's expensive treatment option. Lacking such knowledge and incentives, however, she is exploited by the health-care providers' dictum to maximize profits.

Nobel Laureate Noun 1. Nobel Laureate - winner of a Nobel prize
Nobelist

laureate - someone honored for great achievements; figuratively someone crowned with a laurel wreath
 Kenneth Arrow Kenneth Joseph "Ken" Arrow (born August 23, 1921) is an American economist, joint winner of the Nobel Prize in Economics with John Hicks in 1972, and the youngest person ever to receive this award, at 51.  discussed the problem of doctors, asymmetric information, and ethics in an early book (1974). Doctors who own medical labs or testing equipment have an economic incentive to order tests, and many do so at a rate much higher than average (Armstrong 2005). When such moral hazards exist, the medical community demands--through an ethical code Noun 1. ethical code - a system of principles governing morality and acceptable conduct
ethic

system of rules, system - a complex of methods or rules governing behavior; "they have to operate under a system they oppose"; "that language has a complex system
 dating back twenty-four hundred years--that its members put patient interests ahead of other interests, including those of corporate shareholders. Such a hierarchy of interests is ambiguous in practice, of course, and so the characters of the CEO and the doctor matter a great deal. In particular, we might examine the CEO motives as a basis for analysis. In the case of our backache patient, the CEO must accept that doctors--and hence the CEO as well--have fundamentally competing duties. Both the doctor and the CEO as business manager must restrain themselves in light of the expectations that society has of doctors, whether they are free agents or employees of health-care enterprises.

These two things, the presence of the need of individuals to adhere to adhere to
verb 1. follow, keep, maintain, respect, observe, be true, fulfil, obey, heed, keep to, abide by, be loyal, mind, be constant, be faithful

2.
 duty and the necessity of individuals and their employers to acknowledge the expectations of society, illustrate how Friedman's caveats apply in practical situations. They reveal, too, the subjective dimension of what would seem to be an absolute application of a free-market requirement to maximize profits. Finally, they show how the need to limit profit seeking arises in settings where laws are not at issue and where the ethical customs of society are open to interpretation.

Analogous situations to the doctor can be found in other disciplines. Accountants, lawyers, engineers, journalists, religious leaders, and others have similar but distinctly particular fiduciary standards associated with their vocations. (3) In these and other endeavors, professionals are duty-bound to relegate rel·e·gate  
tr.v. rel·e·gat·ed, rel·e·gat·ing, rel·e·gates
1. To assign to an obscure place, position, or condition.

2. To assign to a particular class or category; classify. See Synonyms at commit.
 profit seeking to secondary status. As with the doctor, managers in these disciplines must recognize the presence of asymmetric information and hold certain important core values above the absolutes of the market. (4) Even econometricians have been called upon to develop a code of ethics in response to numerous problems of asymmetric information in data collection and analysis (Levy and Peart a. 1. Active; lively; brisk; smart; - often applied to convalescents; as, she is quite peart to-day s>.
There was a tricksy girl, I wot, albeit clad in gray,
As peart 
 2008).

One can surmise that social norms and codes for certain professions arose precisely because of issues of client vulnerability. Yet, there are many instances of customer vulnerability where professional codes of conduct are absent. Take, for example, the situation of a traveler in need of urgent car repair to an isolated town with only one service station. A nationwide corporation owns the repair station, and the shop manager faces a decision of whether to maximize profits for the owners (corporate shareholders) or follow a perceived moral duty to put the customer's interests ahead of the company's. To some degree, this problem can be handled adequately by enlightened self-interest Enlightened self-interest is a philosophy in ethics which states that persons who act to further the interests of others (or the interests of the group or groups to which they belong), ultimately serve their own self-interest.  in the marketplace. The car repair shop manager might decide to be honest and not take advantage of the customer to thereby promote the corporation's reputation for honesty. In this way, the manager could justify favoring the customer's interests on the grounds that doing so creates a relationship resulting in greater profits in the long run (Novak 1990). (5) Accordingly, absent a professional code of conduct, the institution of competitive markets itself--through repeat business-can create incentives for behavior that conform to Verb 1. conform to - satisfy a condition or restriction; "Does this paper meet the requirements for the degree?"
fit, meet

coordinate - be co-ordinated; "These activities coordinate well"
 ethical standards, even if the motives for action are avaricious av·a·ri·cious  
adj.
Immoderately desirous of wealth or gain; greedy.



ava·ri
 (Smith 1981; McCloskey 2006).

Relying upon the consequentialist incentive of enlightened self-interest to handle all problems of moral hazard Moral Hazard

The risk that a party to a transaction has not entered into the contract in good faith, has provided misleading information about its assets, liabilities or credit capacity, or has an incentive to take unusual risks in a desperate attempt to earn a profit before the
 is problematical. This is the case, for example, when sellers do not anticipate repeat business, when buyers themselves are not responsible for paying (e.g., third-party insurance payers), and when providers can sustain asymmetric information and lack of transparency. It can also occur when managers' bonuses are tied to short-term rather than long-term goals. In such situations, greed can lead to free riding and inefficiency that can be substantial in certain industries (health care, for one). Resolving such problems is not easy, but Friedman and Smith provide fairly consistent arguments at both the theoretical and the practical levels to advocate for market principles restricted by compelling individual duties and social customs.

Smith and Friedman differ greatly, however, in their attempts to explain the complex human behaviors that provide a rationale for moral duties. For his part, Smith offers a nuanced account in The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1982) for how society inculcates young people in concepts of duty and virtue so that, as adults, they might come to acquire self-control. This socialization socialization /so·cial·iza·tion/ (so?shal-i-za´shun) the process by which society integrates the individual and the individual learns to behave in socially acceptable ways.

so·cial·i·za·tion
n.
 process relies upon the cultivation of mutual sympathy ("fellow-feeling") that is genuinely felt. It demands that self-interest be constrained and often superseded by other motives.

In many ways, Smith's model individual is similar to Friedman's, but a key distinction is with Friedman's ethical framework. Smith is a virtue ethicist eth·i·cist   also e·thi·cian
n.
A specialist in ethics.

Noun 1. ethicist - a philosopher who specializes in ethics
ethician

philosopher - a specialist in philosophy
 who argues (with Hume) that although ethical behavior produces good consequences, the foundation for ethical behavior lies in the emotional connections of individuals rather than in rational calculations of enlightened self-interest.

Not unlike Aristotle and other of his predecessors, Smith holds virtue to be its own reward. Smith states, "Sympathy ... cannot, in any sense, be regarded as a selfish principle" (1982, 317). Smith's moral sentiments model can then readily explain how and why an economic actor could behave with duty to customers, even in cases of one-time interactions and with pervasive asymmetric information, that is, in cases in which enlightened self-interest breaks down.

Friedman's model cannot do the same, and his ideal manager, we will see, is logically inconsistent. According to Friedman, business executives are bound by the principal-agent relationship Principal-agent relationship

Occurs when one person, an agent, acts on the behalf of another person, the principal.
 to operate in a deontological de·on·tol·o·gy  
n.
Ethical theory concerned with duties and rights.



[Greek deon, deont-, obligation, necessity (from ; see deu-1 in Indo-European roots) +
 or duty-based ethical manner up the chain of command with their superiors and shareholders. Simultaneously, they are to pursue a purely consequentialist striving to maximize profits and to disallow To exclude; reject; deny the force or validity of.

The term disallow is applied to such things as an insurance company's refusal to pay a claim.
 intrusions into their conduct such as Smith's moral sympathy. Managers thereby face a moral dilemma. If they accept the notion that deontological moral duties should guide behavior, and if deontological moral duties require that everyone be treated in the same manner, then preferring one group (shareholders) over other stakeholders on purely consequentialist grounds is morally untenable. How can this be resolved? Terry Price (2008) addresses the question using Kantian logic, but the result may be difficult to generalize and apply in practical situations.

In addition, it is also unclear in Friedman's argument how and why managers come to acquire fidelity to the concept of moral duty in the first place. Friedman does not provide an adequate answer and so the logical fallacy Noun 1. logical fallacy - a fallacy in logical argumentation
fallacy, false belief - a misconception resulting from incorrect reasoning

hysteron proteron - the logical fallacy of using as a true premise a proposition that is yet to be proved
 in his argument is this: that capitalism clearly requires duty-bound managers, but capitalist institutions cannot create or sustain the concept of duty. Paul Heyne Paul T. Heyne (1931-2000) was a lecturer in economics for nearly a quarter century at the University of Washington in Seattle, United States.

Heyne received two divinity degrees from Concordia Seminary in St.
 (1995), an advocate of markets, succinctly argues this point:
   The market requires moral foundations which cannot be created by
   market transactions themselves. Moral foundations are nurtured in
   communities--in families, neighborhoods, religious fellowships,
   local political associations, and other voluntary groups. By
   fostering the steady disintegration of these communities, market
   transactions may tend over time to undermine the moral foundations
   upon which they rest.


This is the first lacuna lacuna /la·cu·na/ (lah-ku´nah) pl. lacu´nae   [L.]
1. a small pit or hollow cavity.

2. a defect or gap, as in the field of vision (scotoma).
 in Friedman's concept of the manager--that managers must be duty-bound to shareholders but cannot be duty-bound to customers, workers, suppliers, and other stakeholders. The important exception is if profits can be enhanced by appearing to be duty-bound to other stakeholders, that is, to appear morally committed to social concerns if doing so enhances community relations 1. The relationship between military and civilian communities.
2. Those public affairs programs that address issues of interest to the general public, business, academia, veterans, Service organizations, military-related associations, and other non-news media entities.
, worker efforts, and so on. Managers thus have a dualistic ethical personality.

This duality at the level of theory suggests a second and practical feature of Friedman's argument: Managers are morally authentic when responding up the chain of command but possibly deliberately inauthentic when manipulating down the corporate hierarchy (as long as no moral norms are broken). The second lacuna in Friedman's concept of the manager then reveals how Smith and he diverge at an instrumental level. While both see ethics as achieving some beneficial outcomes, Smith's concept of the ethical person is fundamentally nonconsequentialist. Smith uses a virtue-based behavioral model, incorporating intuitions and emotions to study human motivations, while Friedman relies more upon consequentialist calculations of self-interest and a loose deontology de·on·tol·o·gy  
n.
Ethical theory concerned with duties and rights.



[Greek deon, deont-, obligation, necessity (from ; see deu-1 in Indo-European roots) +
 to establish the duties of managers to corporate shareholders.

Profits and Motivation

In his Nobel Prize Nobel Prize, award given for outstanding achievement in physics, chemistry, physiology or medicine, peace, or literature. The awards were established by the will of Alfred Nobel, who left a fund to provide annual prizes in the five areas listed above.  address, Douglass North Douglass Cecil North (born November 5, 1920) is co-recipient (with Robert William Fogel of the 1993 Nobel Prize in Economics. In the words of the Nobel Committee, North and Fogel were awarded the prize "for having renewed research in economic history by applying economic theory and  (1994) argued that neoclassical economics is a poor vehicle for understanding the development of markets because it generally ignores the role of institutions and path dependencies over time. Similarly, Kenneth Arrow observed of doctors, institutions, and ethics that, "one might regard professional ethics professional ethics,
n the rules governing the conduct, transactions, and relationships within a profession and among its publics.

professional ethics liability,
n 1.
 as an example of an institution which fills in some measure the gap created by the corresponding failure of the price system" (Arrow 1974, 36-37). Both comments illustrate aspects of Friedman's model, which is that it is arguably helpful in identifying the instrumental role of managers but inadequate for understanding the motives and full range of managers' duties. (6)

Friedman's model is limited for one because he argues that maximizing profits should direct the manager's activities without explaining the reasons for profit maximizing being the single and best motivator for managers and entrepreneurs. The notion that profit is or should be the overarching motivator is problematic for several reasons. First, it contradicts a common understanding and empirical research about the ways successful business leaders actually motivate in practice. A slew of management and leadership literature indicates that managers and entrepreneurs are not motivated primarily by profit maximizing (Adams 1984; Hawken 1987; Osterberg 1993; Ray and Rinzler 1993; Ray and Renesch 1994; Peale, Blanchard, and Peale 1996; Harmen and Porter 1997; Blanchard 1997; and Pfeffer 1998). Rather, they are inspired by ideas and ideals related to an enterprise.

Second and following from the first point, Friedman's model fails as an explanation for manager motivation because it relies on a neoclassical economic model ill-designed to provide such explanation. The neoclassical economic model is a black box containing virtually no behavioral information about the psychological sources of meaning. It explains well how businesses become efficient at generating profits but does not account for the motives that drive individuals to produce those profits. It can explain, for example, how F. W. Taylor's scientific management's time studies, standardization, and mechanical view of management can increase efficiency to generate higher profits in business, but it cannot account for the drive, creativity, and circumspection cir·cum·spec·tion  
n.
The state or quality of being circumspect. See Synonyms at prudence.

Noun 1. circumspection - knowing how to avoid embarrassment or distress; "the servants showed great tact and discretion"
 that impel im·pel  
tr.v. im·pelled, im·pel·ling, im·pels
1. To urge to action through moral pressure; drive: I was impelled by events to take a stand.

2. To drive forward; propel.
 individuals to build successful institutions. Moreover, it does not explain the fundamental reasons for engaging the process in the first place. It simply explains process without reflecting on the merit of the activity. It is vulnerable therefore to criticisms such as Peter Drucker's, who reputedly re·put·ed  
adj.
Generally supposed to be such. See Synonyms at supposed.



re·puted·ly adv.

Adv. 1.
 said, "There is nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done at all" (Office of Federal Procurement Policy, 2004, 16).

Third, Friedman's model is inadequate because there are so many better alternatives to it. A more helpful approach, for example, can be found in the recent intellectual history of entrepreneurship, which explains a wide range of managerial motivations (Kalantaridis 2004). Here, we find how profit is a central concern for managers (especially entrepreneurs) but not the only or even main source of meaning and motivation. Rather, managers and risk-taking mavericks tend to be motivated by the desire to achieve, build, overtake competitors, produce the best, be first to market, or attain some self-actualizing goal or set of goals. Rivalry, for one, is a potent motivator. As Adam Smith noted, rivalry and emulation, spurred by competition, is usually sufficient to induce "the very greatest exertions" (1981, 760). Such rivalry, as David McCleland argues in The Achieving Society (1961), is spurred by the desire to excel and is a psychological process and not simply a desire for a specific outcome, such as maximizing profits.

Other, more anecdotal observations support Smith's and McCleland's arguments. For example, John Kay's sample of twentieth-century innovations--DNA, computing, antibiotics, television, and the green revolution in agriculture--illustrates how "financial incentives play ... only a small part [in their discovery], and the financial rewards for the discoverers were not great.... The principal motives appear to be the excitement of the process of discovery, and the social rewards offered to the renowned scientist" (2004a, 268). Even Donald Trump admits that, "Money was never a big motivator for me, except as a way to keep score. The real excitement is playing the game" (BrainyQuote). Motivating goals can even relate to transpersonal trans·per·son·al  
adj.
Transcending or reaching beyond the personal or individual.
 or altruistic objectives. Frank (2004, 79), for example, found that workers in companies with "socially responsible" profiles were willing to accept wages far below firms that did not. In the end then, a wide range of other explanations supersede To obliterate, replace, make void, or useless.

Supersede means to take the place of, as by reason of superior worth or right. A recently enacted statute that repeals an older law is said to supersede the prior legislation.
 Friedman's model as an explanation of manager motivation.

Fourth, Friedman's model does not account for the inspirational sentiments underlying managerial motives to maximize profits. Although he suggests that enlightened self-interest motivates managers to maximize profits, managers might just as easily adopt a pretense of such sentiments to mask their greed. In such circumstances, a savvy (but cynical) manager might even promote the goals of corporate social responsibility in the hope that these might increase productivity, customer loyalty, and ultimately ... profits. This sort of approach is not farfetched. It befits the modus operandi [Latin, Method of working.] A term used by law enforcement authorities to describe the particular manner in which a crime is committed.

The term modus operandi is most commonly used in criminal cases. It is sometimes referred to by its initials, M.O.
 of many "opportunistic pseudo-transformational leader(s)" observed by Terry Price (2003, 72).

Adam Smith's model of behavioral psychology behavioral psychology
n.
See behaviorism.
, in contrast, provides a clearer rationale for the moral sentiments empowering responsible business practices. For Smith, the natural sentiment of sympathy (fellow-feeling) is the source of moral virtue that "cannot, in any sense, be regarded as a selfish principle" (1982, 317). In practice, it engenders caution and truthfulness. The reason for this is simple--because people are adept at discerning the feelings of others similar to themselves, they can detect deceit. Accordingly, "the prudent man is always sincere, and feels horror at the very thought of exposing himself to the disgrace which attends upon the detection of falsehood" (Smith 1982, 214). Although exceptions in the form of superb emotional fakers do exist, it is difficult for most people to sustain emotional fictions. Most can intuit when another (for our purposes, a manager) says something he or she does not really believe, and the resulting punishment of alienation and disgust when individuals are caught in deception is usually sufficient to minimize widespread hypocrisy.

Having established the reasons and support for fellow-feeling and honesty, Smith goes on to note that ambitious people frequently do not know for certain what they are pursuing. Their objectives are bound up within a social context so that acceptance and status among their peers becomes their strongest desire (1982, 213). As Smith notes: "It is not ease or pleasure, but always honour, of one kind or another, though frequently an honour very ill understood, that the ambitious man really pursues" (1982, 65, emphasis added). When placed in the context of business, this means that managers learn to generate profit for the sake of survival (their own and their firm's), but this is not to say that they are motivated by profit per se or that they operate best from a psychological perspective in which profit maximization is at the center.

Fifth and finally, Friedman's model not only fails to account for certain inspirational sentiments, it also fails to recognize the importance of intuition in motivation. Here, Frank Knight's Risk, Uncertainty, and Profit (1921) is particularly helpful to an understanding of the role of intuition in management and, in particular, to transformational leadership. In Knight's view, risk is an attribute of a business project for which reasonably well-known probabilities exist. If insurance markets are deep enough, for example, one can buy policies to protect against virtually any risk. Uncertainty, on the other hand, is a situation in which not enough information exists to make reasonable assessments of probability. No amount of planning or logical assessment can resolve the uncertainty and so no insurance can be bought to offset its hazards. In environments of uncertainty, intuition may be a vital input in production (Kay 2004a, 2004b). As Trump reflects: "Experience taught me a few things. One is to listen to your gut, no matter how good something sounds on paper" (BrainyQuote).

If it is true that intuition and emotion (right-brain functions) are sometimes of greater use to managers than logical, cost-benefit calculations (left-brain functions), then managers may need to develop imagination, spontaneity, curiosity, creativity, and connectivity--all forms of moral imagination--a topic to be addressed next (Goleman 1995, Elster 1998).

Obliquity and Organizational Transformation

While most contemporary management theorists acknowledge Smith's and Friedman's theories as helpful, these and other early microeconomic mi·cro·ec·o·nom·ics  
n. (used with a sing. verb)
The study of the operations of the components of a national economy, such as individual firms, households, and consumers.
 theories are thought to be overly narrow and limited. They consequently have been largely replaced with approaches that are more expansive and holistic.

John Kay, corporate consultant and former business school dean at Oxford University, proffers one such new approach that emphasizes "obliquity." Here, Kay argues that the best way to reach a profit objective is not always to head directly for it but to approach it from the side, that is, obliquely. Such an approach is preferable in dynamic situations where systems are "complex, imperfectly understood, and change their nature as we engage with them" (Kay 2004b). The approach is especially helpful in multifaceted, interdependent business organizations where, typically, there is no single, simple, and correct strategy for running operations. In these dynamic situations--whether the industry is new or mature, has adopted technology slowly or quickly, is publicly or privately held, has extensive or weak government regulations, is led by a founding entrepreneur or hired managers, has low or high margins--managers must balance a variety of competing internal and external demands to resolve problems. While Friedman's simple admonishment to maximize profits has an important place in this environment, it is certainly not an exclusive prescription for business development.

Kay recognizes the limits of traditional direct approaches to management problems and goes on to explain that managers who focus on the simple, well-defined objective of profit maximization often fail miserably. They make the mistake, in his view, of "underestimating the complexity of the system with which they (deal) and the value of the traditional knowledge they (inherit)" (ibid.). A better approach, he believes, is one that provides managers with a holistic perspective of the corporation; that is, one that enables managers to adapt to and succeed in a changing world. To buttress his point, Kay observes how few neoclassical microeconomists are hired by businesses. This, he suggests, is partly because microeconomic theorists rely on simplistically direct, ahistorical a·his·tor·i·cal  
adj.
Unconcerned with or unrelated to history, historical development, or tradition: "All of this is totally ahistorical.
 approaches that do not account for the path-dependent nature of evolutionary business enterprises. Further, the standard model fails to portray adequately the complex psychological incentives that motivate today's managers.

The paucity of the standard model that Kay describes highlights not just the limits of microeconomic theory but also the failure of economists to account for one of the theory's central tenets-Smith's notion of sympathy. Sympathy or fellow-feeling is critical to good management, for by it, "we place ourselves in [another's] situation, we conceive ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter as it were into his body, and become in some measure the same person with him " (1982, 9). Sympathy forms the basis of moral imagination and enables managers to deeply understand and appreciate the employees, investors, suppliers, customers, and other stakeholders crucial to the success of commercial enterprises (Werhane 1999; Moberg and Seabright 2000). While number crunching Refers to computers running mathematical, scientific or CAD applications, which perform large amounts of calculations. See number cruncher.

(application, jargon) number crunching
 skills and consequentialist approaches that emphasize profit maximization are important, these alone are insufficient for good management as both today's management theorists and Adam Smith recognized.

The key points raised here are first, that Smith's concept of human motivation does allow for a dominant role to be played by nonpecuniary motives; and second, that Smith's approach is based on a nonconsequentialist model of moral sentiments that inspires good management. Smith lays out the biological and psychological case for human instincts that lead to the formation of moral rules and norms (Wight 2007; Evensky 2005). While these moral rules serve useful instrumental purposes, they arise from an intuitive psychology that operates through virtue ethics. Given this and within Smith's moral framework, a company might come to represent the best aspirations of its stakeholders, not just financial rewards for its shareholders. Decision-making might reflect a concern for creating a process and generating outcomes that uphold self-actualizing interests (Hawken 1987). Not unlike Michael Porter and Mark Kramer's notion of "building shared values" as an approach to corporate social responsibility, managers might generate loyalty and efficiency that more than compensate for the company's costs (Porter and Kramer 2006, 13).

Conclusion

This article challenges Friedman's doctrine that the pursuit of profit is and should be the manager's exclusive duty. As shown here, Friedman's thesis based on arguments of commutative justice COMMUTATIVE JUSTICE. That virtue whose object is, to render to every one what belongs to him, as nearly as may be, or that which governs contracts.
     2. The word commutative is derived from commutare, which signifies to exchange. Lepage, El. du Dr. ch. 1, art.
, freedom, and economic efficiency does not claim that managers are relieved from the constraints of civil and moral laws. To the contrary, his argument maintains that ethical precepts delimit de·lim·it   also de·lim·i·tate
tr.v. de·lim·it·ed also de·lim·i·tat·ed, de·lim·it·ing also de·lim·i·tat·ing, de·lim·its also de·lim·i·tates
To establish the limits or boundaries of; demarcate.
 and create the foundation for ethical business practices and markets. Friedman's notion of profit maximization, in short, is not synonymous with selfish individualism. Rather, it advocates consideration of others and self-restraint or, in Adam Smith's terminology, sympathy (fellow-feeling) and self-command.

Friedman's argument does, however, raise a logical contradiction. Because moral tenets come as bundles of duties and obligations--often impossible to untangle--they cannot be resolved through simple formulae or defined in terms of profit motivation. Some motive or set of motives other than profit maximization is necessary, and sometimes these other motives can conflict with the profit motive. A business manager, for example, who believes it is her duty to be loyal to the owners' interests, might also believe it is her moral duty to tell the truth--even if doing so might lower profits. James and Rassekh (2000, 671, f2) report that Friedman, in a personal communication, agreed that in such a situation, truth telling to outsiders was a moral obligation of the business manager even if this lowered shareholders' profits. This particular example arose in the specific context of threatened third-party property rights that, to Friedman, might represent a core human right on par with freedom.

For Friedman, the fiduciary aspect of the principal-agent agreement is paramount; hence, honesty is a critical virtue. Honesty is not, however, the only moral virtue relevant to managers, and these other moral virtues become apparent in practice. A manager might easily find him or herself in a position of having to decide, for example, whether or not to uphold shareholder interests when doing so threatens the selfish personal interests of the manager. He or she might also have to decide about whether or not to tell the truth (a form of honesty) when doing so could jeopardize the interests of employees, suppliers, and other stakeholders. In these sorts of situations, relying exclusively upon the principal-agent agreement, the moral virtue of honesty, and profit maximization is unhelpful. Other values and virtues are necessary. Friedman's formula does not account for these and effectively boxes-in managers, forcing them to be only consequentialist in their dealings with stakeholders. This is Friedman's first major gap or lacuna.

Friedman's second lacuna involves his insistence on profit maximization at the expense of important motivational issues in management. While the pursuit of self-actualizing incentives that increase worker loyalty, motivation, and efficiency would be accepted by Friedman under the rubric RUBRIC, civil law. The title or inscription of any law or statute, because the copyists formerly drew and painted the title of laws and statutes rubro colore, in red letters. Ayl. Pand. B. 1, t. 8; Diet. do Juris. h.t.  of enlightened self-interest, his requirement that managers calculate the expected gains and losses from having such nonpecuniary drives and then pretend to possess them undermines the strength and efficacy of the approach. Such a consequentialist reckoning ultimately fails to recognize the genuine relationships of managers as well as the authentic sympathy and passion (Smith's fellow-feeling) that inspire managers, workers, and customers. Hence, this tactic fails to account for moral imagination--a construct that cannot be conjured up along narrowly rational and self-interested grounds.

Given these shortcomings and to offset these lacunae, this article supports a subtler version of Friedman's directive. It acknowledges that profit maximization using all legal and ethical means remains an insightful model of resource allocation resource allocation Managed care The constellation of activities and decisions which form the basis for prioritizing health care needs . It proffers, however, that this metagoal can at times be achieved obliquely by placing other objectives ahead of profit. For example, cultivating a genuine virtue ethic (as in Adam Smith) may achieve this goal, but not in a purely consequentialist manner. In this way, it is hoped, the manager might have a focused, yet more consistently authentic and humane, moral framework to guide his or her behavior.

References

Adams, John Adams, John, 2d President of the United States
Adams, John, 1735–1826, 2d President of the United States (1797–1801), b. Quincy (then in Braintree), Mass., grad. Harvard, 1755.
 D., ed. 1984. Transforming Work: A Collection of Organizational Transformation Readings. Alexandria, Va.: Miles River Press.

Armstrong, David. 2005. "MRI 1. (application) MRI - Magnetic Resonance Imaging.
2. MRI - Measurement Requirements and Interface.
 and CT Centers Offer Doctors Way to Profit on Scans." The Wall Street Journal. May 2, A1.

Arrow, Kenneth. 1974. The Limits of Organization. New York: Norton.

Blanchard, Kenneth, et al. 1997. Managing by Values. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.

BrainyQuote. ND. "Donald Trump Quotes." Available at http://www.brainyquote.com. Accessed March 19, 2005.

Calkins, Martin J., and Patricia H. Werhane. 1998. "Adam Smith, Aristotle, and the Virtues of Commerce." The Journal of Value Inquiry 32 (March): 43-60.

Elster, Jon. 1998. "Emotions and Economic Theory." Journal of Economic Literature 36, no. 1 (March): 47-74.

Evensky, Jerry. 2001. "Adam Smith's Lost Legacy." Southern Economic Journal 67, no. 3: 497-517.

--. 2005. "Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments: On Morals and Why They Matter to a Liberal Society of Free People and Free Markets." Journal of Economic Perspectives 19, no. 3:109-30.

Frank, Robert. 2004. What Price the Moral High Ground? Ethical Dilemmas in Competitive Environments. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Freeman, R. Edward. 2006. "The Wal-Mart Effect and Business, Ethics, and Society." Academy of Management Perspectives 20, no. 3 (August): 38-40.

Friedman, Milton. 1962. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press The University of Chicago Press is the largest university press in the United States. It is operated by the University of Chicago and publishes a wide variety of academic titles, including The Chicago Manual of Style, dozens of academic journals, including .

--. 1970. "The Social Responsibility of Business Is To Increase Its Profits." New York Times Sunday Magazine. September 13, 1970, 32.

Goleman, Daniel. 1995. Emotional Intelligence: Why It Can Matter More than IQ. New York: Bantam, 1995.

Grant, Colin. 1991. "Friedman Fallacies." Journal of Business Ethics 10:907-14.

Harman, Willis, and Maya Porter, eds. 1997. The New Business of Business: Sharing Responsibility for a Positive Global Future. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.

Hawken, Paul. 1987. Growing a Business. New York: Simon and Schuster.

Heyne, Paul. 1995. "Moral Criticisms of Markets." The Senior Economist 10, no. 4 (April).

James, Harvey S., Jr., and Farhad Rassekh. "Smith, Friedman, and Self-Interest in Ethical Society." Business Ethics Quarterly 10, no. 3:659-74.

Kalantaridis, Christos. 2004. Understanding the Entrepreneur: An Institutional Perspective. Hants, U.K.: Ashgate.

Kay, John. 2004a. Culture and Prosperity: The Truth About Markets--Why Some Nations Are Rich but Most Remain Poor. New York: HarperBusiness.

--. 2004b. "Obliquity." Financial Times (January 17). Accessed at http://www.johnkay.com/strategy/317.

Knight, Frank. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. New York: Houghton Mifflin.

Levy, David, and Sandra J. Peart. 2008. "Inducing Greater Transparency: Towards the Establishment of Ethical Rules for Econometrics." Eastern Economic Journal 34:103-114.

McCleland, David. 1961. The Achieving Society. Princeton: Van Nostrad.

McCloskey, Deirdre. 2006. The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Moberg, Dennis J., and Mark A. Seabright. 2000. "The Development of Moral Imagination." Business Ethics Quarterly 10 (October): 845-84.

North, Douglass C. 1994. "Economic Performance Through Time." American Economic Review 84, no. 3 (June): 359-68.

Novak , Michael. 1990. Toward a Theology of the Corporation. Revised edition. Washington, D.C., The AEI AEI American Enterprise Institute
AEI Archive of European Integration
AEI Australian Education International
AEI Automotive Engineering International
AEI Australian Education Index
AEI Albert Einstein Institute
 Press. (Orig. pub. 1981.)

Office of Federal Procurement Policy. Seven Steps to Performance-Based Service Acquisition. 2004. Available from http://www.acquisition.gov/comp/seven_steps/ library/SevenSteps_execversion.pdf. Accessed August 7, 2006.

Osterberg, Rolf. 1993. Corporate Renaissance: Business as an Adventure in Human Development. Mill Valley, Calif.: Nataraj Publishing.

Peale, Norman Vincent, Kenneth Blanchard, and Norman Peale. 1996. The Power of Ethical Management. New York: Ballantine.

Pfeffer, Jeffrey. 1998. The Human Equation: Building Profits by Putting People First. Cambridge: Harvard University Press The Harvard University Press is a publishing house, a division of Harvard University, that is highly respected in academic publishing. It was established on January 13, 1913. In 2005, it published 220 new titles. .

Price, Terry L. 2003. "The Ethics of Authentic Transformational Leadership." The Leadership Quarterly 14:67-81.

--. 2008. Leadership Ethics: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Cambridge University Press (known colloquially as CUP) is a publisher given a Royal Charter by Henry VIII in 1534, and one of the two privileged presses (the other being Oxford University Press). .

Porter, Michael E., and Mark R. Kramer. 2006. "Strategy and Society: The Link Between Competitive Advantage and Corporate Social Responsibility." Harvard Business Review Harvard Business Review is a general management magazine published since 1922 by Harvard Business School Publishing, owned by the Harvard Business School. A monthly research-based magazine written for business practitioners, it claims a high ranking business readership and  (December): 1-15.

Ray, Michael, and Alan Rinzler, eds. 1993. The New Paradigm New Paradigm

In the investing world, a totally new way of doing things that has a huge effect on business.

Notes:
The word "paradigm" is defined as a pattern or model, and it has been used in science to refer to a theoretical framework.
 in Business: Emerging Strategies for Leadership and Organizational Change. New York: Tarcher/Perigee.

Ray, Michael, and John Renesch, eds. 1994. The New Entrepreneurs: Business Visionaries for the Twenty-first Century. San Francisco: Sterling and Stone.

Sandel, Michael J. 1998. "What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets." The Tanner Lectures on Human Values The Tanner Lectures on Human Values is a multi-university lecture series in the humanities, founded on July 1, 1978, at Clare Hall, Cambridge University, by the American scholar Obert Clark Tanner. . Oxford University (May). Accessed at http://www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/sandel00.pdf.

Smith, Adam. 1981. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by R. H. Campbell and A. S. Skinner. Glasgow Edition. Indianapolis: Liberty Press. (Orig. pub. 1776.)

--. 1982. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Edited by D. D. Raphael and A. L. Macfie. Glasgow Edition. Indianapolis: Liberty Press. (Orig. pub. 1759.)

Werhane, Patricia H. 1999. Moral Imagination and Management Decision Making. The Ruffin Series in Business Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

Wight, Jonathan B. 2007. "The Treatment of Smith's Invisible Hand Invisible Hand

A term coined by economist Adam Smith in his 1776 book "An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations". In his book he states:

"Every individual necessarily labours to render the annual revenue of the society as great as he can.
." The Journal of Economic Education 39, no. 3 (Summer): 341-58.

Young, J. T. 1997. Economics as a Moral Science: The Political Economy of Adam Smith. Cheltenham, U.K.: Edward Elgar.

Martin Calkins

Assistant Professor

College of Management

University of Massachusetts The system includes UMass Amherst, UMass Boston, UMass Dartmouth (affiliated with Cape Cod Community College), UMass Lowell, and the UMass Medical School. It also has an online school called UMassOnline.  

Jonathan B. Wight

Professor of Economics and

International Studies

Robins School of Business

University of Richmond

Notes

(1.) Friedman observes that tax laws may mitigate against this because of the double taxation of corporate profits.

(2.) Adam Smith is equally cynical: "I have never known much good done by those who affected to trade for the public good" (1981, 456). Smith is referring here to merchants who profess to care for society's interests when they are really lobbying for legislation that would earn them economic rent (e.g., through protectionism). Friedman's point is analogous.

(3.) Here, vocation is regarded as a response to a calling.

(4.) What exactly are these absolute laws or institutional rules? Friedman provides only one example, that of the widespread acceptance of wages in a market system based on individual productivity. One can think of many others, such as the widespread acceptance of the legitimacy of fairly elected governments and the widespread adherence to moral injunctions against theft. It should be clear that transaction costs in exchange would be much higher in the absence of widespread acceptance of basic social norms of morality.

(5.) Michael Novak makes this distinction: "[T]here is a difference between maximization of profit and optimization of profit. To aim at maximizing profit--that is, to obtain the greatest profit possible out of every opportunity--is to be greedy in the present at the expense of the future.... By contrast, to optimize profit is to take many other factors besides profit into account, including long-term investment, consumer loyalty, and the sense of a fair service for a fair price" (1990, 51).

(6.) R. Edward Freeman R. Edward Freeman (born December 18, 1951) is an American philosopher and professor of business administration at the Darden School of the University of Virginia. He has also taught at the University of Minnesota and the Wharton School.  argues similarly against approaches that take a "narrow economic view of business," here in terms of criticisms of Wal-Mart (2006).
COPYRIGHT 2008 Acton Institute
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2008 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 Reader Opinion

Title:

Comment:



 

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Title Annotation:Milton Friedman
Author:Calkins, Martin; Wight, Jonathan B.
Publication:Journal of Markets & Morality
Article Type:Critical essay
Date:Sep 22, 2008
Words:6742
Previous Article:Philanthropy, markets, and commercial society: beyond the Hayekian impasse.
Next Article:Milton Friedman on income inequality.
Topics:

Terms of use | Copyright © 2014 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters