Printer Friendly
The Free Library
23,421,980 articles and books


On the diversity of linguistic evidence for conceptual metaphor.

ABSTRACT

In this article my main concern is the linguistic evidence for the view that metaphor is conceptual in nature. Since the fact that there is a great diversity of linguistic evidence for patterns of metaphorical thought has been, by and large, not emphasized enough, I overview a variety of such evidence, which can be derived from the study of different aspects of meaning within a particular language, crosslinguistically, and at a metalinguistic level. However, in itself the variety of linguistic evidence, even though it speaks very strongly for the idea that metaphor is conceptual in nature, is not sufficient to justify it. Therefore, recognizing the fact that claims about our conceptual system A conceptual system is a system that is comprised of non-physical objects, i.e. ideas or concepts. In this context a system is taken to mean "an interrelated, interworking set of objects". Overview
A conceptual systems is simply a model.
 which are based on linguistic analyses alone remain within the "language--thought language" circle, the article discusses also some kinds of nonlinguistic evidence for conceptual metaphors. Psycholinguistic psy·cho·lin·guis·tics  
n. (used with a sing. verb)
The study of the influence of psychological factors on the development, use, and interpretation of language.
 research on metaphorical reasoning is presented as a major source of such nonlinguistic verifications. Drawing on Daniel Barenboim's BBC BBC
 in full British Broadcasting Corp.

Publicly financed broadcasting system in Britain. A private company at its founding in 1922, it was replaced by a public corporation under royal charter in 1927.
 Reith lectures A Reith Lecture is a lecture in a series of annual radio lectures given by leading figures of the day, commissioned by the BBC and broadcast on BBC Radio 4. They were begun in 1948, in honour of the first Director-General of the BBC, John Reith.  of 2006, it is also argued that convergent evidence from language and music may serve to break open the "language--thought language" circle.

"Metaphorical thinking being unavoidable, we might as well relax and enjoy it" (Langacker 2006: 108).

1. Introduction

It is now a common consensus view in cognitive linguistics In linguistics and cognitive science, cognitive linguistics (CL) refers to the school of linguistics that understands language creation, learning, and usage as best explained by reference to human cognition in general.  that, as Lakoff--Johnson (1980: 6) put it, "[m]etaphors as linguistic expressions are possible precisely because there are metaphors in a person's conceptual system". (1) As a mode of thought, so the argument goes, metaphor guides not only our reasoning, but also our emotions, behaviour and actions. In fact, according to according to
prep.
1. As stated or indicated by; on the authority of: according to historians.

2. In keeping with: according to instructions.

3.
 the standard theory, it is due to its conceptual nature that metaphor shows up so abundantly in everyday language as this is the medium via which we conventionally communicate to others about our emotions, thought, behaviour, and actions. (1) The idea that metaphor plays a fundamental role in shaping our conceptual system and in thought has been around in the philosophical and linguistic tradition of Europe much earlier;

Likewise, it is the standard view among cognitive linguists A linguist in the academic sense is a person who studies linguistics. Ambiguously, the word is sometimes also used to refer to a polyglot (one who knows more than 2 languages), or a grammarian, but these two uses of the word are distinct.  that enduring patterns of metaphorical thought, commonly referred to as conventional conceptual metaphors, are frequently motivated, or grounded, by image schemas (such as SOURCE--PATH--GOAL, UP/DOWN, FORCE), which are universal patterns of experience of the human body and its interaction with the world (Johnson 1987, 2005; Lakoff--Johnson 1999). The latter view--known as the thesis of embodiment of conceptual metaphor In cognitive linguistics, conceptual metaphor refers to the understanding of one conceptual domain in terms of another, for example, understanding time in terms of space (e.g. "time flies"). A conceptual domain can be any coherent organization of experience.  constitutes one of the cornerstones of the cognitive approach to metaphor. (2)

Although the embodied experience of the world and the self provides the main motivation for the metaphors "we live by", conceptual metaphors are, by no means, necessarily based on bodily experience. As has been extensively discussed in cognitive linguistic literature, culture is another major source of motivation for conventional metaphors a particular society "lives by". (3) In brief, conceptual metaphors are both universal and language-specific. This, it needs to be noted, should not be taken to imply that universal experience necessarily leads to universal metaphors, since embodied experience can be overridden by cultural factors and cognitive processes Cognitive processes
Thought processes (i.e., reasoning, perception, judgment, memory).

Mentioned in: Psychosocial Disorders
.

It is beyond doubt that the cognitive theory Conitive theory may refer to:
  • Theory of cognitive development, Jean Piaget's theory of development and the theories which spawned from it.
  • Two factor theory of emotion, another cognitive theory.
 of metaphor has had a great impact not only on the study of meaning in language, but also of human behaviour, action, and of understanding, in particular. Yet, as Gibbs--Perlman (2006: 212) rightly note, "[d]espite the tremendous success, and increasing popularity of cognitive linguistic work on metaphor there are numerous criticisms of this research both within and outside linguistics". In this paper, however, the critical appraisal Noun 1. critical appraisal - an appraisal based on careful analytical evaluation
critical analysis

appraisal, assessment - the classification of someone or something with respect to its worth
 of the cognitive theory of metaphor will be taken up very briefly only (section 2.6), (4) as my main concern here is the linguistic evidence for the conceptual nature of metaphor. In my view, the fact that there is a great diversity of linguistic evidence for patterns of metaphorical thought has been, by and large, not emphasized enough. It will thus be the main aim of section 2 to present this variety of evidence, which we can derive from the study of different aspects of meaning within a particular language, crosslinguistically, and at a metalinguistic level. In section 3, in turn, I will present some of the recent psycholinguistic research which strongly supports the central claim of cognitive linguistics that metaphor is a matter of thought, reasoning, and action.

Viewed from a more distant perspective, my overarching o·ver·arch·ing  
adj.
1. Forming an arch overhead or above: overarching branches.

2. Extending over or throughout: "I am not sure whether the missing ingredient . . .
 aim here is to resume the discussion of the conceptual nature of metaphor. My own contribution towards this end will be presented in section 4, where, relying on a sample of my case study of the metaphor LIFE IS MUSIC, which formed the backbone of Daniel Barenboim's BBC Reith lectures of 2006, I will argue that reliance on the speakers' and listeners' conscious awareness of a particular conceptual metaphor may provide direct evidence for the role of metaphor in understanding and in action as well as in structuring creative thought.

2. Diversity of linguistic evidence

2.1. Systematicity of metaphorical expressions

The most common kind of evidence for making claims about the conceptual nature of metaphor derives from the systematicity of metaphorical expressions which are used to talk about a particular target concept. Consider, first, a data sample from the Macmillan English dictionary (MED):

1) a. The baby arrived just after midnight.

b. I set out to become a doctor, but it never worked out.

c. She went through life without ever knowing the truth.

d. This event moved his life in an unexpected direction.

e. It's all been an uphill struggle.

f. He embarked on a new career.

g. They remembered the departed in their prayers.

Clearly, all the expressions in italics are conventional means of talking about birth, life and death in terms of the expressions which in their basic sense are used to talk about journeys. The examples represent but a fraction of the "journey lexicon" which has been conventionally extended to acquire metaphorical senses designating some aspect of the concept of LIFE, including the concepts of BIRTH and DEATH. The key of the argument here is that the systematicity of metaphorical linguistic expressions in (1) manifests particular patterns of metaphorical thought, and that without the metaphorical reasoning based on these patterns it would be difficult (if possible at all) not only to talk, for example, about progress, choices or goals in life, but also to think about them and act accordingly. The relevant conceptual metaphors are commonly named as: BIRTH IS ARRIVAL, LIFE IS A JOURNEY, DEATH IS DEPARTURE. Observe also that these metaphors have a clear motivation in our basic bodily experience of directed motion along a path which we acquire (with some persistence and effort needed to learn how to walk) in early childhood, and which stays meaningful throughout our whole life in the form of what is labelled: the SOURCE--PATH GOAL image schema An image schema is a recurring structure of, or within, our cognitive processes, which establishes patterns of understanding and reasoning. Image schemas emerge from our bodily interactions, linguistic experience and historical context. .

Note further that underlying our metaphorical understanding of, e.g., progress, difficulties or goals in life, there is an intricate system of metaphors called the EVENT STRUCTURE METAPHOR (Lakoff 1993). Some of the constituent metaphors (or else, the mappings) of the EVENT STRUCTURE METAPHOR are given in (2); for illustration, reference to some of their linguistic manifestations which were listed in (1) is given in brackets.

2) a. STATES ARE LOCATIONS (see (1a))

b. CHANGE IS MOTION (see (1b))

C. CAUSES ARE FORCES (see (1d))

d. ACTION IS SELF-PROPELLED MOTION (see (1c))

e. PURPOSES ARE DESTINATIONS (see (1d, e))

f. LONG-TERMED PURPOSEFUL ACTIVITIES ARE JOURNEYS (see (1 c, f)).

It appears, then, that LIFE IS A JOURNEY is a specific metaphor which inherits the structure from the EVENT STRUCTURE system. Moreover, understanding life as a purposeful activity represents a more general pattern of metaphorical thought in terms of which other purposeful activities can be conceived as a journey (cf., e.g.,: LOVE IS A JOURNEY, ARGUMENT IS A JOURNEY). The EVENT STRUCTURE METAPHOR itself is a complex system of metaphors which interact in providing coherent understanding of some of the fundamental abstract concept, such as: STATE, CHANGE, CAUSATION causation

Relation that holds between two temporally simultaneous or successive events when the first event (the cause) brings about the other (the effect). According to David Hume, when we say of two types of object or event that “X causes Y” (e.g.
, PURPOSE and ACTION. Most importantly Adv. 1. most importantly - above and beyond all other consideration; "above all, you must be independent"
above all, most especially
, since such concepts constitute the very core of our conceptual system, "the fact that they are conceptualized metaphorically shows that metaphor is central to ordinary abstract thought" (Lakoff 1993: 222).

2.2. Polysemy and novel semantic extensions of everyday language

As has been repeatedly shown in cognitive linguistic literature, polysemy is the norm for language. In the case of English, for example, 97 of the 100 most common words in English The list below of most common words in English, like any superlative list, cannot be definitive. It is based on an analysis of the Oxford English Corpus of over a thousand million words, and represents one study done by Oxford Online, associated with the Oxford English Dictionary.  are polysemous (see Gibbs 1994: 157). Crucially, a great variety of research has demonstrated that (aside metonymy metonymy (mĭtŏn`əmē), figure of speech in which an attribute of a thing or something closely related to it is substituted for the thing itself. Thus, "sweat" can mean "hard labor," and "Capitol Hill" represents the U.S. Congress. ) conceptual metaphor is one of the two driving forces behind polysemy both in the lexicon and in grammar. For the present purpose, let us consider a fraction of the lexicon which we conventionally employ in English to talk about the functioning of mind, as in:

3) a. It took me ages to latch on to what she was talking about. (CALD CALD

chronic active liver disease.
)

b. He ground out the same ideas that he's been talking about for twenty years TWENTY YEARS. The lapse of twenty years raises a presumption of certain facts, and after such a time, the party against whom the presumption has been raised, will be required to prove a negative to establish his rights.
     2.
.

c. She's running out of steam and I don't believe she'll ever manage to finish this novel.

The verbs latch, grind, and the expression run out of steam in their basic sense refer to the functioning of some mechanical device or machine, while in their extended metaphorical senses they characterize some functional aspect of the mind. The conceptual metaphor which motivates semantic extensions such as those in (3) is called MIND IS A MACHINE. Observe also that this pattern of metaphorical thinking is motivated by cultural experience in a broad sense of the term.

Note now that, as our understanding of the functioning of the mind has become more sophisticated and precise in the computer age, within the life-span of one generation a new vocabulary from the COMPUTER domain has become a conventional means of talking about the MIND. The examples in (4) are but a fraction of this new lexicon of MIND:

4) a. I wish I could erase some files from my memory.

b. My (operating) system crashed.

c. You gave me a lot of input to think about.

d. My disc is full, I won't process anything more today.

The data in (3) and (4) are telling in two respects. Firstly, they show that, even though the expressions in (3) might be said to be "linguistically frozen", the MIND IS A MACHINE metaphor is still conceptually "alive", as is revealed by the expressions in (4). Secondly, since this new lexicon of MIND has already become conventional (at least for the computer generation), the MIND IS A MACHINE metaphor appears to have a more specific variant MIND IS A COMPUTER. In brief, the system of conceptual metaphors is "alive" not only in that it motivates novel semantic extensions in a language, but also in that it itself may change to reflect new patterns of metaphorical thinking.

2.3. Metaphorical language This article or section may contain original research or unverified claims.

Please help Wikipedia by adding references. See the for details.
This article has been tagged since September 2007.
 of everyday and literary metaphors Contrary to the established wisdom which holds that the genius of great poets and writers gives rise to the majority of metaphors we know, it is now an established view in cognitive linguistics that, as Lakoff--Turner (1989: xi-xii) put it:

"Great poets can speak to us because they use the modes of thought we all possess", of which "metaphor is a primary tool for understanding our world and our selves". It has become evident that cognitive mechanisms that are commonly employed in the poetic reworking of ordinary metaphors reside in: (i) extending the elements of the source domain, i.e. introducing new elements to the conventional mappings; (ii) elaboration of the well-established elements of the source domain; (iii) questioning the validity of conventional metaphors; and (iv) combing conventional conceptual metaphors. (5)

To give one illustration, let me refer to Freeman's (2000) study of Emily Dickinson, and her analysis of the metaphors of TIME in the following poem:

5) They say that "Time assuages"-- Time never did assuage-- actual suffering strengthens As sinews do--with Age-- Time is a test of Trouble-- not a Remedy-- such it prove, it prove too There was no Malady-- In this poem, Dickinson questions our well-established conventional metaphor TIME IS A HEALER healer Mainstream medicine A romantic synonym for physician. See Traditional healing. , which is manifested linguistically in, for example, a common saying "time heals all wounds". (6) As Freeman (2000: 267) notes, Dickinson denies the TIME IS A HEALER metaphor aiming to show that "true suffering is everlasting everlasting or immortelle (ĭm'ôrtĕl`), names for numerous plants characterized by papery or chaffy flowers that retain their form and often their color when dried and are used for winter bouquets and decorations. ". Rejecting the idea of TIME as "an agentive figure working against the ground of suffering", she "replaces it by reversing figure and ground": in the

for the relevant overviews see, for example, Krzeszowski (1988) and Jakel (1999).

(2) For more on image schemas and the idea of embodiment of meaning see, for example, Gibbs (2005), Johnson (2005), Grady (2005).

(3) For an overview, see, for example, Kovecses (2005); see also Gorska--Radden (2005).

(4) For a recent contribution to this debate see, in particular, Kovecses (2008).

(5) See, e.g., Gibbs (1994), Turner (1987, 1996); for overviews see Kovecses (2002) and Gibbs (2008).

(6) This understanding of TIME as CAUSER is motivated by our everyday metaphorical reasoning about external "agentless" events as actions. In our everyday understanding of events we frequently "ascribe as·cribe  
tr.v. as·cribed, as·crib·ing, as·cribes
1. To attribute to a specified cause, source, or origin: "Other people ascribe his exclusion from the canon to an unsubtle form of racism" 
 the occurrence of a particular event to a nonincidental property indispensably involved in that event" (Lakoff--Turner 1989: 37), and thereby establish a causal link between the occurrence (e.g. the healing of a wound or disappearance of pain) and some nonincidental property of the event's occurrence (cf. events always require time for their occurrence and the passage of time is, in our folk view, an indispensable property of time). As soon as the causal link is established, we can metaphorically portray an event as an action with a wilful wil·ful  
adj.
Variant of willful.


wilful or US willful
Adjective

1. determined to do things in one's own way: a wilful and insubordinate child 
 agent of some sort (i.e. we can apply the EVENTS ARE ACTIONS metaphor, see Lakoff 1993, and also section 2 above). Note further that TIME is also personified as, e.g., a THIEF (as in: Time has stolen her youth/beauty), a DESTROYER destroyer, class of warship very fast relative to its length, generally equipped with torpedos, antisubmarine equipment, and medium-caliber and antiaircraft guns. The newest destroyers are equipped with guided missiles as their chief offensive weapon.  ( as in: Time has destroyed her youth/beauty); for more on personification personification, figure of speech in which inanimate objects or abstract ideas are endowed with human qualities, e.g., allegorical morality plays where characters include Good Deeds, Beauty, and Death.  of TIME in literature, see also Lakoff--Turner (1989: 34-43).

second part of the poem, "trouble" is selected as "the figure against the ground of time". In effect, Dickinson conceives of time as a criterion by which a suffering can be evaluated. Moreover, as Freeman argues, "[t]he words test and prove suggest the methodology of science, by which actual experience can be empirically verified", and in effect, "[w]hat is being suggested in this poem is that some metaphors are better than others in enabling us to understand life's experiences" (Freeman 2000: 267).

For our immediate purpose, the tight conceptual bond which underlies the conventional and the literary usage of metaphorical language can be said to provide strong evidence for the conceptual nature of conventional metaphors and for the role which conceptual metaphors play in our making sense of the world and of our selves. Given the conceptual nature of metaphor, an alternative "scenario" wherein conventional and literary metaphors had nothing in common, is highly unlikely, if possible at all.

2.4. Crosslinguistic studies and metaphorical thought

2.4.1. Lexicalization patterns

Since Talmy's (1985) pioneering study, lexical coding of conceptual categories, i.e. lexicalization in the synchronic syn·chron·ic  
adj.
1. Synchronous.

2. Of or relating to the study of phenomena, such as linguistic features, or of events of a particular time, without reference to their historical context.
 sense of the term, (7) has been extensively studied in a crosslinguistic perspective. Focusing on metaphorical extensions, let us briefly consider the coding of motion event, which has been the best documented case of lexicalization so far (see, in particular, Slobin 2004; Filipovic 2007).

Of the three characteristic components of a motion event--(FACT OF) MOTION, MANNER (OF MOTION), and PATH (OF MOTION), the latter served as basis for drawing the typological contrast between two major kinds of conflation (database) conflation - Combining or blending of two or more versions of a text; confusion or mixing up. Conflation algorithms are used in databases.  patterns which are typical of the so-called satellite-framed languages (S-languages, represented by most European languages (including English) other than Romance languages, and also Finno-Ugric, Chinese and Ojibwa (an Algonquian language Noun 1. Algonquian language - family of North American Indian languages spoken from Labrador to South Carolina and west to the Great Plains
Algonquian, Algonquin
)) on the one hand, and of the so-called verb-framed languages (V-languages, represented by Romance, Semitic, Japanese, and Polynesian) on the other hand. In an S-language such as English, PATH is coded overtly in a SATELLITE to the verb, i.e. an element associated with the verb (e.g., a particle or an affix affix v. 1) to attach something to real estate in a permanent way, including planting trees and shrubs, constructing a building, or adding to existing improvements. ), while in a single verb root (or lexeme (grammar) lexeme - A minimal lexical unit of a language. Lexical analysis converts strings in a language into a list of lexemes. For a programming language these word-like pieces would include keywords, identifiers, literals and punctutation. ) MOTION is conflated with MANNER, as in (6a): (8)

6) a. He ran into the house.

b. Eve girdi.

'He entered the house.' c. Eve kosarak girdi.

'He entered the house running.' By contrast, in a verb-framed language such as Turkish, PATH is conflated in a single verb root (or lexeme), as in (6b), while MANNER is coded overtly by, for example, participles derived from manner verbs (see, for example, running in (6c)) or manner adverbs. (9) Moreover, numerous empirical studies Empirical studies in social sciences are when the research ends are based on evidence and not just theory. This is done to comply with the scientific method that asserts the objective discovery of knowledge based on verifiable facts of evidence.  of the literal language show that in a V-language the manner information tends to be left out unexpressed, i.e. (6b) represents the default coding, while (6c) is used only when the manner information becomes particularly salient (see Ozacaliskan 2005 and the literature cited therein). It is also evident that, unlike V-language speakers, speakers of S-languages pay far more "linguistic attention" to MANNER--they regularly and easily provide information about MANNER, using their default conflation pattern (as in (6a)) as well as a variety of alternative lexical means of encoding MANNER (participles, adverbs, etc.). This is particularly interesting, in view of the fact that speakers of a V-language like Turkish, even though they cannot easily code MANNER at the level of motion verbs, have at their disposal a variety of other lexical means which they may use to encode (1) To assign a code to represent data, such as a parts code. Contrast with decode.

(2) To convert from one format or signal to another. See codec and D/A converter.

(3) The term is sometimes erroneously used for "encrypt.
 manner (see, for example, (6c); see Ozacaliskan 2005:211). Note also that there is ample evidence from crosslinguistic empirical studies of literal language that this effect of the typological contrast in conflation patterns crosscuts boundaries of culture, language family, and geographical location (see Ozacaliskan 2005: 210).

Let us now turn to metaphorical motion events. It has been shown repeatedly that motion in space is a very frequent source domain for metaphorical understanding of diverse abstract concepts. In English, for example, motion verbs are systematically extended to designate a variety of concepts, including:

7) a. TIME (e.g.: time is flying, hours crawl by).

b. IDEAS (e.g.: Her message came across easily; The idea sprang back into her mind).

C. EMOTIONS (e.g.: A hint of emotion entered his voice for the first time (MED)).

d. ECONOMY (e.g.: a run-down of stock levels)

e. LIFE (see the data in (1) above).

For our purpose, the results of Ozacaliskan's (2005) study of metaphorical motion events in English and Turkish are immediately relevant. Relying on a huge body of data from written texts and also on elicited responses from native speakers, Ozacaliskan has shown that the above described typological effect of the lexicalization patterns is highly apparent not only in the literal uses of the lexicon, but also becomes evident in the metaphorical extensions of the lexicon in these two languages. Summing up her results, she observes that English speakers and writers encode manner of motion at a higher rate than Turkish speakers and writers--"both in the use of motion verbs (59% compared to 27%) and in using alternative lexical means to encode it (133 instances to 81 instances)" (Ozacaliskan 2005: 236).

With regard to patterns of metaphorical thought, Ozacaliskan's results cannot be overestimated. Crucially, they indicate that "the contrast in the encoding of MANNER in the source domain is also likely to have effects on our conceptualization con·cep·tu·al·ize  
v. con·cep·tu·al·ized, con·cep·tu·al·iz·ing, con·cep·tu·al·iz·es

v.tr.
To form a concept or concepts of, and especially to interpret in a conceptual way:
 of the target domain of a metaphorical mapping" (2005: 238-239). For example, English speakers are more likely to have a more elaborate representation of TIME AS A MOVING ENTITY, with the ability to detect and report more fine-grained distinctions in their experience of time, as in (8a):

8) a. time creeps, time crawls, time drags b. time passes

For Turkish speakers, on the other hand, the same pattern of metaphorical thought motivates "a more general sense of time passage as motion along a path [see (8b)], with fewer shades of Noun 1. shades of - something that reminds you of someone or something; "aren't there shades of 1948 here?"
reminder - an experience that causes you to remember something
 difference in the way time is conceptualized to move" (2005: 239).

When put in general terms, crosslinguistic studies of lexicalization patterns may be said to provide a direct insight into similarities and differences in patterns of metaphorical thought, and thereby into similarities and differences in understanding of abstract concepts by speakers of different languages. At this point, however, a word of caution is in order. Ozacaliskan's study did not involve any cognitive tasks and thus, as the author herself explains, "the claims raised about the potential effects of language on cognition cognition

Act or process of knowing. Cognition includes every mental process that may be described as an experience of knowing (including perceiving, recognizing, conceiving, and reasoning), as distinguished from an experience of feeling or of willing.
 are only a prediction ... and therefore should be regarded as in need of future empirical verification" (2005: 242, note 4).

2.4.2. Grammaticalization patterns

Crosslinguistic research into diachronic di·a·chron·ic
adj.
Of or concerned with phenomena as they change through time.
 semantic change In diachronic (or historical) linguistics, semantic change is a change in one of the meanings of a word. Every word has a variety of senses and connotations which can be added, removed, or altered over time, often to the extent that cognates across space and time have very  abounds in arguments for cognitive foundations of grammar (see e.g. Heine--Claudi--Hunnemeyer 1991; Heine 1997; Heine--Kuteva 2002), and what is immediately relevant, conceptual metaphor is often recognized as "the driving force" (see, e.g., Heine--Claudi--Hunnemeyer 1991: 226) behind the so-called grammaticalization, i.e. a (typically) unidirectional process which leads from more concrete lexical (i.e. less grammatical) forms and constructions to more abstract (i.e. more grammatical) ones. (10)

To illustrate, lexical verbs denoting physical motion in space, such as the English go in (9a):

9) a. He is going to the woods.

b. He is going to go to/work in/buy the woods.

may develop into grammatical forms or construction with a temporal sense of future, as was the case of the English going to (see (9b)). This grammaticalization pattern has been attested in typologically different languages (see Heine--Kuteva 2002: 161-163); aside Germanic languages like English, also in Romance languages (cf. the French aller 'to go (to)' as the future marker), Nilo-Saharan languages (cf. the Bari tu 'go' as the determinative future marker), and Dravidian (cf. the Tamil poo 'go' as the auxiliary marking future tense future tense
n.
A verb tense expressing future time.

Noun 1. future tense - a verb tense that expresses actions or states in the future
future
), to name but a few.

To take another crosslinguistically very common grammaticalization pattern, lexemes denoting physical objects or their parts may be metaphorically extended to acquire far more abstract senses, as is illustrated by the body part back in English, which developed a purely spatial sense of 'outside area behind sth' (cf. The kids are playing out the back (MED)). And here again, the same path of change has also occurred in typologically diverse languages, such as Icelandic, Halia, and Tzoltzil (see Heine--Kuteva 2002: 47-48).

Crucially, crosslinguistic studies into the unidirectionality of metaphorical grammaticalization patterns have led Heine--Claudi--Hunnemeyer (1991: 48) to postulate postulate: see axiom.  a striking generalization--a chain of categorial metaphors, given in (10):

10) PERSON > OBJECT > SPACE > TIME > QUALITY, where each category can be understood as representing a conceptual domain (such as PERSON or TIME) which may function as the source domain for conceptualizing any other domain to its right. In effect, the chain consists of a number of categorial metaphors, such as SPACE IS AN OBJECT, TIME IS SPACE, etc. By way of illustration, consider the lexeme megbe 'back' in Ewe, a Niger-Congo language (see Heine--Claudi--Hunnemeyer 1991: 65-69, 222-225). In its basic sense, it designates a body part, hence a concept of the OBJECT category (see (11)).
11) epe       megbe     fa
3SG.POSS      back      be.cold
'His back is cold.'
12) ele       xo        a         megbe
3SG-be        house     DEF       behind
'He is behind the house.'
13) eku       Ie        e-megbe
2SG-die       be        3SG.POSS-behind
'He died after him.'
14) e-tsi     megbe
3SG-remain behind
'He is backward/dull.'


And its metaphorically extended senses include: spatial location as in (12), temporal sense as in (13), and the sense of mentally retarded Noun 1. mentally retarded - people collectively who are mentally retarded; "he started a school for the retarded"
developmentally challenged, retarded
, as in (14), hence the category of QUALITY. And in this case again, the chain of categorial metaphors in (10) crosses the boundaries of language families and cultures (see Heine--Kuteva 2002).

In sum, the unidirectional arrangement of grammaticalization patterns in (10) shows that "concepts which are more immediately accessible to human experience are employed for the expression of less accessible, more abstract concepts" (Heine--Claudi--Hunnemeyer 1991:51) which strongly suggests that the driving force behind them are indeed metaphorical patterns of thought.

2.5. Metalanguage of science

Shifting to metalinguistic manifestations of metaphorical thought, let us now take the science of language as the source of data in point. Specifically, let us have a look at Langacker's discussion of two fundamental issues that keep recurring re·cur  
intr.v. re·curred, re·cur·ring, re·curs
1. To happen, come up, or show up again or repeatedly.

2. To return to one's attention or memory.

3. To return in thought or discourse.
 in linguistics--continuity and discreteness (Langacker 2006). These issues pertain to pertain to
verb relate to, concern, refer to, regard, be part of, belong to, apply to, bear on, befit, be relevant to, be appropriate to, appertain to
 a whole range of descriptive and theoretical problems, of which Langacker considers genetic relationships of languages, grammatical constituency, (7) For the diachronic sense of this term and its principled prin·ci·pled  
adj.
Based on, marked by, or manifesting principle: a principled decision; a highly principled person.
 distinction from grammaticalization see Brinton and Traugott (2005).

(8) Examples in (6) after Ozacaliskan (2005: 209-210).

(9) This characterization should not be taken to refer to "'pure" S- and V-languages, but to prototypes of such language only. In a prototypical S-language like English, for example, aside a very rich lexicon of MANNER verbs (e.g.: run, fly, crawl), there is also a sizeable group of PATH verbs (e.g.: enter, ascend), and also some neutral verbs, such as move where neither PATH nor MANNER component is conflated, and only (the FACT OF) MOTION is coded.

(10) In grammaticalization literature, the role of conceptual metaphor in the development of grammatical meanings has been a matter of much debate. Other mechanisms which are often mentioned in this context include metonymy, inference and implicature im·plic·a·ture  
n.
1. The aspect of meaning that a speaker conveys, implies, or suggests without directly expressing. Although the utterance "Can you pass the salt?"
, subjectification; for an overview see, in particular, Brinton and Traugott (2005), and also Langacker (1998).

ency, determinacy de·ter·mi·na·cy  
n.
1. The quality or condition of being determinate.

2. The condition of being determined or characterized.
 of syntax, and polysemy. When discussing the latter, Langacker gives a critical assessment of the so-called network metaphor, which underlined his well-known network model of complex categories (Langacker 1987), compares it with the continuous field metaphor, which lies behind Allwood's (2003) continuous meaning potential model and Zlatev's (2003) use-potential model, and concludes that the network metaphor, even though it gave rise to insightful analyses of polysemy, is "misleading by virtue of being overly discrete" (2006: 146); on the other hand, "the continuous field metaphor is misleading by virtue of being insufficiently discrete" (2006: 146). By way of reconciliation, he refers to Langacker's (2004) mountain peak metaphor, which, despite its own limitations, "has the proper mixture of discreteness and continuity" (2006: 147). The characterization of the mountain peak metaphor is a prime example of the metaphorical metalanguage, and therefore it is worth quoting here in extenso in ex·ten·so  
adv.
At full length: an article reprinted in extenso in a later collection.



[Latin in ext
:

15)

Instead, we might distort things less by comparing an element's" range of meanings to a mountain range, which occupies a continuous expanse but is very uneven owing to owing to
prep.
Because of; on account of: I couldn't attend, owing to illness.

owing to prepdebido a, por causa de 
 rises, depressions, peaks, and valleys. Counting the senses of a lexical item would then be analogous to counting the peaks in a mountain range: how many there are depends on how salient they have to be before we count them, and they appear discrete in the first place only because we ignore how they grade into one another at lower altitudes. The uncertainty we sometimes experience in determining which particular sense an expression instantiates on a given occasion is then to be expected. The uses in question are like points in the valley between two peaks'. It is essentially an arbitrary matter whether we assign such points to one peak, to the other, to both, or to neither [all emphases mine].

(Langacker 2004: 48)

Needless to say, from the cognitive perspective, it is not only the metalanguage of linguistics that is metaphorical, but also the way we conceive of Verb 1. conceive of - form a mental image of something that is not present or that is not the case; "Can you conceive of him as the president?"
envisage, ideate, imagine
 language, in the first place (see the seminal paper by Reddy 1979). As Langacker put it: "In one way or another, virtually all thinking about language--both on the part of linguists and by ordinary speakers--is metaphorical in nature" (2006: 107). And crucially, formalist for·mal·ism  
n.
1. Rigorous or excessive adherence to recognized forms, as in religion or art.

2. An instance of rigorous or excessive adherence to recognized forms.

3.
 and functionalist func·tion·al·ism  
n.
1. The doctrine that the function of an object should determine its design and materials.

2. A doctrine stressing purpose, practicality, and utility.

3.
 approaches to language differ in the extent to which their metaphors imply discreteness, with formalist metaphors tending towards discreteness, since it "offers the attractive prospect of rigorous, economical, and elegant formalizations revealing the true mechanisms of language at every level" (Langacker 2006: 108). And yet, as Langacker shows, the discreteness metaphors that formalists rely upon are "not just inappropriate but seriously misleading" (2006: 108). For, even though viewing a particular phenomenon as discrete or continuous is a matter of construal con·strue  
v. con·strued, con·stru·ing, con·strues

v.tr.
1. To adduce or explain the meaning of; interpret: construed my smile as assent. See Synonyms at explain.
, the choice is by no means arbitrary. Instead, as Langacker argues, it should reflect the way the world is intrinsically (see 2006:114). Crucially, moreover, a typical phenomenon is far too complex for one metaphor to be able to grasp all its intricacies. As in the case of our everyday conventional metaphors, a particular metaphor employed in a scientific theory may highlight a particular aspect of the phenomenon while hiding some other aspect or aspects, as is the case with the wave metaphor and the particle metaphor that are used in modern physics to describe the nature of light (this example is also referred to by Langacker 2006:114). In such cases, a particular metaphor is misleading whenever it is claimed to describe and explain the nature of a given phenomenon as a whole.

2.6. Concluding remarks

The variety of evidence from metaphorical language discussed thus far itself speaks very strongly for the conceptual nature of metaphor. Still cognitive linguists are well aware of the fact that reliance on language in making claims about metaphorical thought has some evident drawbacks. On the one hand, the cognitive theory of metaphor is still in need of clear and generally agreed upon Adj. 1. agreed upon - constituted or contracted by stipulation or agreement; "stipulatory obligations"
stipulatory

noncontroversial, uncontroversial - not likely to arouse controversy
 criteria for identifying, on the one hand, metaphorical expressions and conceptual metaphors on the other hand. (11) Recently, however, some interesting proposals have been made which aim at making the analysis of language data more reliable. One such proposal is the so-called principled polysemy approach, which was developed by Tyler-Evans (2003) and Evans (2004), and which considerably constrains rampant polysemy in general, and excessive metaphorical extensions, in particular. (12)

Equally relevant is the counterargument of "circularity", which is often posed against the logic of research practice in cognitive linguistics: "Analysts first examine linguistic expressions, enough so to infer the possible presence of underlying metaphorical mappings, and then test this possibility by referring back to language" (Gibbs-Perlman 2006:215). This "language-to-thought-to-language circle", however, is, as Gibbs-Perlman rightly observe, "not particular to cognitive linguistics"--formal approaches like generative linguistics Generative linguistics is a school of thought within linguistics that makes use of the concept of a generative grammar. The term "generative grammar" is used in different ways by different people, and the term "generative linguistics" therefore has a range of different, though  are also confronted with the same problem "in identifying various syntactic Dealing with language rules (syntax). See syntax.  patterns" (2006: 215). A way out to break open this circle is to provide some nonlinguistic evidence which would converge with claims based on metaphorical language. And, indeed, there is an increasing body of nonlinguistic evidence supporting the view that metaphor is conceptual in nature. The issues is commonly discussed under the rubric RUBRIC, civil law. The title or inscription of any law or statute, because the copyists formerly drew and painted the title of laws and statutes rubro colore, in red letters. Ayl. Pand. B. 1, t. 8; Diet. do Juris. h.t.  of nonlinguistic realizations of conceptual metaphor, such as in films, cartoons, drawings, sculptures, advertisements, symbols, myths, dreams, and gestures. (13) Naturally, a great variety of nonlinguistic manifestations is to be expected if, as cognitive linguists argue, metaphor is a matter of thought, perception, and action.

3. Psycholinguistic research

By now, the view that metaphor is conceptual in nature has gained a lot of support from many psycholinguistic studies (for overviews see, e.g., Gibbs (1994, 2008), Giora (2003), and Gibbs-Perlman (2006). For our immediate purpose, I will present briefly one psycholinguistic approach to understanding narratives and characterize a new line of experimental research into the so-called simulation semantics.

3.1. Understanding narratives

In this section I will discuss a pilot study which I conducted during the spring semester se·mes·ter  
n.
One of two divisions of 15 to 18 weeks each of an academic year.



[German, from Latin (cursus) s
 2008 in the Institute of English Studies English studies is an academic discipline that includes the study of literatures written in the English language (including literatures from the U.K., U.S., Ireland, Canada, Australia, New Zealand, Hong Kong, the Philippines, India, South Africa, and the Middle East, among other  at Warsaw University. The objectives of my study were twofold. Firstly, as in Gibbs's (2005) study, I wanted to establish how conceptual metaphor operates in inferencing based on narrative texts. Secondly, my aim was to see how the participants (forty-nine graduate students of different age groups (aged 20-45) who were all fluent in English) would cope with the situation of discrepancy between the explicit linguistic coding and the detailed understanding of the narratives. The experiment was done during the first class of the course on Conceptual metaphor, and this assured that about 90% of the students had no prior idea of the cognitive theory of metaphor. Part 1 of the experiment was entirely based on the study by Gibbs (2005: 125-129)--the same data was used and the same questions were asked. Students were first instructed to read two stories about love relationship given here in (16) below:

16) Story A
   Imagine that you are a single person. A friend sets you up on a
   blind date. You really like this person and start dating a lot.
   Your relationship was moving along in a good direction. But then it
   got even better. The relationship felt like it was the best you
   ever had. This continues to this day. No matter what happens, the
   two of you are quite happy together.


Story B
   Imagine that you are a single person. A friend sets you up on a
   blind date. You really like this person and start dating a lot.
   Your relationship was moving along in a good direction. But then
   you encountered some difficulties. The relationship did not feel
   the same as before. This lasted for some time. No matter how hard
   you two tried, the two of you were not getting along.


Next, the participants answered a series of questions which were designed to test their intuitions about the relationships in the two stories and the implicit image schema of SOURCE--PATH--GOAL that underlies the source domain of the LOVE RELATIONSHIPS ARE JOURNEYS metaphor. The questions are listed in (17) below:

17) (i) Which relationship progressed further?

(ii) Which relationship was progressing faster at the beginning?

(iii) Which relationship is progressing faster at present?

(iv) Which relationship progressed more along a straight line?

(v) In which relationship were the individuals heading in the same direction?

Similarly to Gibbs's (2005) study, there was a lot of regularity in the students' answers: in the case of the first question 96% of participants selected Story A (the "smooth journey" story, as Gibbs refers to it). Answers to the second question were divided into 51% choices of Story A and 49%--of Story B (in Gibbs's terms: the "interrupted journey" story). For the third question, 77,5% of participants chose the smooth journey story. The same story was also selected in the case of the fourth and the fifth question by, respectively, 90% and 88% of participants. These results are very much in line with the findings reported in Gibbs (2005: 128-129)), wherein the smooth journey story was selected as the answer to the first and the third question by 90% of the participants, and to forth and the fifth questions by 60% and 80% respectively, while the second question, just as in my study, resulted in a split with 45% selecting the smooth journey and 55% the interrupted journey.14 Observe that the very close match between Gibbs's findings based on his study of native speakers of English and the results of my pilot study where the participants were native speakers of Polish who are very fluent in English does not seem coincidental co·in·ci·den·tal  
adj.
1. Occurring as or resulting from coincidence.

2. Happening or existing at the same time.



co·in
. On the contrary, it suggests that English and Polish participants drew inferences on the basis of an analogous pattern of metaphorical thought. This comes as no surprise, since speakers of these two languages systematically talk about LOVE in terms various aspects of JOURNEY. Needless to say, the universal image schema of SOURCEPATH--GOAL provides experiential ex·pe·ri·en·tial  
adj.
Relating to or derived from experience.



ex·peri·en
 grounding for this conceptual metaphor irrespective of irrespective of
prep.
Without consideration of; regardless of.

irrespective of
preposition despite 
 the language we speak.

In Part 2 of my study, students were first instructed to read the two stories again and find expressions which explicitly tell something about: (i) the distance of the journey travelled; (ii) its speed; (iii) the shape of the path; and (iv) the direction of motion of the travellers. As predicted, no such expressions were found. Next, students were asked to reread Verb 1. reread - read anew; read again; "He re-read her letters to him"
read - interpret something that is written or printed; "read the advertisement"; "Have you read Salman Rushdie?"
 the questions (see (17)) and decide whether any of them ask about these four aspects of the journey. This time students had no problem with finding positive answers: they had no doubts that question (i) is about the distance of the journey travelled, question (ii) and (iii) about the speed, question (iv)--about the shape of the path, and question (v) the direction of motion of the travellers. Finally, students were instructed to read the two stories once more and find whether there are any expressions which explicitly describe relationships as being like a journey. As expected, they could find only one such expression, namely:

18) Your relationship was moving along in a good direction.

The final and, for my purpose, the main part of my study resided in an open discussion of the results of Part 1 and Part 2 of the experiment. My aim here was to find how the students would account for the situation of discrepancy between the explicit linguistic coding and their detailed understanding of the narratives, and the way the students drew inferences in particular. It is most interesting to note that, having realized that there is hardly any linguistic support in the text of the narratives for their detailed answers, some students were so much taken aback that they kept rereading the stories again and again! They accepted the results as "real", rather than a trick of some sort, only when they had learnt about the results of the original study by Gibbs. Clearly, in our folk view of language we so much believe in meaning being contained "right there" in the words themselves (see Reddy 1979) that we feel very uncomfortable to find that there is some implicit mechanism of meaning construction, such as the conceptual metaphor, to which we have no direct access. In brief, we do not feel at ease with our cognitive unconscious even when we have strong evidence for the role it plays in our metaphorical reasoning. (15)

(15) The term cognitive unconscious is after Lakoff-Johnson (1999).

And as for the students' attempted accounts of the results of Part 1 of the study, even though the majority did not want to take a risk, a few provided explanations, such as: "something hidden must be going on" and "this is how we normally think about love". In these explanations we can see that some implicit conventional pattern of metaphorical thought, residing in understanding of the conceptual domain of LOVE RELATIONSHIPS in terms of the JOURNEY domain, has emerged from the cognitive unconscious.

3.2. Simulation semantics

Simulation semantics is a new line of psycholinguistic research which has been inspired by recent studies in cognitive science cognitive science

Interdisciplinary study that attempts to explain the cognitive processes of humans and some higher animals in terms of the manipulation of symbols using computational rules.
 showing that many aspects of perception are coupled with action (see Gibbs 2005:118). Crucially, it has been claimed in cognitive literature that "[a] significant part of how we understand the behavior of others is accomplished through real and simulated body actions", which in Damasio's (1999, 2003) terms are "as-if-body loops" (Gibbs 2005: 118, emphasis mine). Relying on these findings, simulation semantics "gives a primary role to embodied simulations in drawing inferences from various metaphorical and nonmetaphorical language" (see Gibbs-Perlman 2006: 218, and the literature cited therein). This perspective has been also adopted by Gibbs (2005) in his approach to image schemas and, in effect, to his idea that embodied simulations are involved in understanding metaphorical language which is based on image schematic reasoning.

To be more precise, according to Gibbs, "image schematic reasoning is always being recreated by the body as people continue to engage in sensorimotor sensorimotor /sen·so·ri·mo·tor/ (sen?sor-e-mo´ter) both sensory and motor.

sen·so·ri·mo·tor
adj.
Of, relating to, or combining the functions of the sensory and motor activities.
 behaviors related to [e.g.] BALANCE, RESISTENCE, SOURCE-PATH-GOAL" (2005: 116). By claiming that image schemas are psychologically real he means, therefore, that they play "a critical role in people's real-time thought and linguistic processes" (2005:114). This view, as Gibbs (2005) and Gibbs-Perlman (2006) argue, has gained support from various experimental studies into the embodied metaphor understanding. For the sake of illustration, let me refer to one such study by Gibbs (in press), which is discussed in Gibbs-Perlman (2006: 224-225). (16) The study aimed to test the hypothesis that, when engaged in understanding of simple narratives which involve conceptual metaphors (e.g. LOVE RELATIONSHIPS ARE JOURNEYS), people imaginatively simulate themselves into a bodily action (such as motion along some path), which facilitates their metaphorical understanding of a certain aspect of the abstract target concept (e.g. the idea that love relationships can move along a path toward a goal). The hypothesis was tested on the basis of the stories given here in (16) in section 3.1. above and their nonmetaphorical counterparts (i.e. without the statement Your relationship was moving in a good direction) in two experimental conditions. In one condition, after hearing either the successful smooth journey story or the unsuccessful interrupted journey story in either the metaphorical or in the nonmetaphorical version, participants were asked to physically walk towards an object (a yellow ball), 40 feet away. In the other experimental condition, participants were instructed to imagine walking to the object after hearing one of the stories and press a stopwatch as soon as they imagined arriving at the object. As for the first physical walking condition, analyses of the walking times as well as of the length of walking showed that there was a significant difference in how each of the metaphorical stories was physically enacted: walking times were generally longer for the successful story, and so were the distances covered. Similar results were obtained for the imagined walking condition. This, according to Gibbs-Perlman, suggests that metaphorical understanding of narratives which was prompted by the metaphorical linguistic expression--Your relationship was moving in a good direction--"is not purely abstract, but embodied" in that aspects of manner and path of movement in a particular relationship as they were conceived by the participants subsequently affected the manner and path of the participants' actual walking as well as their imagined walking as they thought about the stories in the experimental condition (see 2006: 225). In a word, metaphor understanding appears to be an embodied simulation process.

3.3. Concluding remarks

On the basis of psycholinguistic data claims have been made that what cognitive linguists describe as conventional metaphorical expressions speakers/listeners often regarded as literal speech. For example, according to Keysar et al. (2000), "expressions like He was depressed are entirely literal, and are not motivated by a conceptual metaphor such as SAD IS DOWN" (Gibbs-Perlman 2006: 215). Arguments of this kind, however, do not take into account the fact that with repeated use semantic structures, whether metaphorical or otherwise, gain the status of cognitive routines which speakers activate fully automatically. In effect, in the case of well-entrenched metaphorical extensions, reliance on the categorizing relationship holding between a particular extended sense and some other more basic sense is no longer necessary (see Langacker 1987: 58, 68-69). Note also that the "fading away" of the metaphor, or, in other words Adv. 1. in other words - otherwise stated; "in other words, we are broke"
put differently
, the loss of motivation can be regarded as "a special case of the gradual decrease in analyzability that is typical for lexical items" (Langacker 2008: 224, fn. 11). Clearly, this dynamic aspect of language has an obvious implication for empirical studies of metaphorical expressions--variation in speakers judgments is to be expected as it is a direct reflection of the development of meanings in language on the one hand, and of nature of language as a repository of symbolic resources which are mastered as cognitive routines on the other hand.

4. Speakers' and listeners' conscious awareness, and music

In this section I will aim to show that speakers and listeners may have clear intuitions about the conceptual nature of metaphor and, crucially, they may discuss explicitly the function of a particular novel metaphor in understanding and in action. The case in point is the novel conceptual metaphor LIFE IS MUSIC, which was created by conductor and pianist Daniel Barenboim Daniel Barenboim (born November 15, 1942) is a pianist and conductor. He lives in Berlin and holds citizenship in Argentina, Israel, and Spain. He was born in Buenos Aires, Argentina; his parents were Russian Ashkenazi Jews. ; the metaphor formed the backbone of a series of five lectures titled In the beginning was sound which were delivered by Barenboim as the BBC Reith lectures of 2006. Barenboim's explicitly stated aim was to convince his audience that music (classical music and jazz in particular), which he characterizes as "sound with thought" (LD-1), can express not only our feelings and emotions, but may also serve as a powerful tool of thought and communication.

Within the framework of conceptual metaphor, LIFE IS MUSIC can be regarded as a megametaphor which extends through the whole lecture series, whose function is to unify a number of specific metaphors having an individual, social, political or cultural aspect of LIFE as their target domains. Consider, for instance, how Barenboim proceeds to convince his audience that the impact of a single critical event in life on our perception of whatever preceded it and whatever will follow is best expressed and understood through music. Referring to a musical example he later intends to play, he first notes:

19) the moment where there comes a fantastic vertical pressure on the horizontal floor of the music, and that that moment you know that the music cannot continue any more the way it was before, such as the world was not the same after the 9th November of 1938, or the 9th November of 1989, or the 11th September of 2001--events that have changed everything both towards the future and towards the past (L3).

The specific novel metaphor that he employs can be stated as: A CRITICAL EVENT (IN THE COURSE OF LIFE) IS A VERTICAL PRESSURE (ON THE HORIZONTAL FLOOR OF MUSIC). The musical example played to support the argument are a few bars from the last movement of the ninth symphony by Beethoven where the text is: "And the cherub cherub (chĕr`əb), plural

cherubim, kind of angel. Cherubim were probably thought of in the ancient Middle East as composite creatures like the winged creatures of Assyria. In Jewish tradition, they are described (Ezek.
 stat stat
adv.
With no delay.

adj.
Immediate.


STAT Stat! Clinical medicine adverb Fast, quickly, immediately, schnell, vite Lab medicine noun
 for Gott, for Gott, for Gott". Observe that the UP/DOWN and the FORCE image schemas, which provide the structure and basic "logic" of the source domain of this metaphor, are evoked first through language (see the expressions vertical pressure, horizontal floor in (19)), and then by means of pitch and volume of the music played. It is thus evident that, with the help of the conceptual metaphor in question, Barenboim and his audience simultaneously participate in two modes of thought and communication: music and language.

As one more illustration, (17) consider how Barenboim reconstructs for his audience the way he managed to find a resolution in his debate with his friend Edward Said Edward Wadie Saïd, Arabic: إدوارد وديع سعيد,  over the Oslo process. He notes first that for a long time they kept having very hefty arguments until one day Barenboim said to his friend:

20) It doesn't really matter if Oslo is right or wrong, it will never work because the relation between content and time is erroneous." I said, "This I have learned from music." And he looked at me and said, "What are you talking about?" And I said to him, "The preparation for the beginning of the Oslo discussions was practically non-existent, much too quick. And the process itself, once the discussion started, was very slow, and then it was interrupted, and then they said they would meet next Tuesday, and then it was cancelled on Monday, and then they met again a month later, and everything. It had no chance. " And I sat down at the piano and I showed to him what I meant (LD-1).

At this point, Barenboim played a few bars of a very majestic, slow introduction of the Pathetique sonata of Beethoven, and then moved on to play a few bars of the main movement--Allegro, and recalled that he had told his friend that "Oslo, the equivalent of Oslo would be if I would play the introduction very fast and without any preparation of anything--in other words:" [he played a few bars of the introduction very fast], and commented: "You would not understand anything what I am doing. And then I would get to the main allegro and I will play:" [he played only one note from the allegro], which made his audience respond with laughter; he then he played a few more notes of the allegro--few at a time with pauses, to which his audience reacted with applause. Finally, he closed up his argument by saying that his discussion with his friend Said "stopped from that moment on about Oslo because we both agreed it wouldn't work, for different reasons" (LD-1).

In this case, the specific novel metaphor which Barenboim employs can be stated as: A SUCCESSFUL EVENT SCHEDULE IS AN APPROPRIATE RELATION BETWEEN CONTENT AND TIME IN MUSIC. At the linguistic level, this metaphor extends over the paragraph in (20), providing understanding of why the timing of the events as Barenboim has described it could not lead to a successful outcome of the Oslo process (see the passage in bold in (20)). And, here again, Barenboim's musical example is meant to support his verbal message and shift his audience to a different mode of thought and communication--music. Note also that Barenboim explicitly observes that his audience "wouldn't understand anything", if the relation between content and time in the introduction of the Pathetique sonata was of the type he played in its very fast version. Observe further that Barenboim's communication via the musical mode is crystal clear to his audience--they react with laughter and applause.18 Evidently, both for Barenboim and his audience the presently considered specific instantiation (programming) instantiation - Producing a more defined version of some object by replacing variables with values (or other variables).

1. In object-oriented programming, producing a particular object from its class template.
 of the metaphor LIFE IS MUSIC is a mode of thought which provides a clear understanding of the situation at hand, and also functions as a successful means of communication. It needs to be emphasized, however, that when Barenboim originally employed the same specific metaphor in his debate with Edward Said, it played a role not only in providing an understanding of the situation to which they both could agree (although "for different reasons"), but--more importantly--it brought about a change in their action and behaviour--they stopped arguing.

To sum up, in certain types of discourse, such as lectures, speakers and hearers may openly get involved in a creative metaphorical thought and reasoning, being consciously aware of a particular novel metaphor and relying on it in constructing arguments and in achieving their persuasive aims. Moreover, the data discussed in this section show that we have yet another kind of convergent evidence for the conceptual nature of metaphor--from language and music. 19

5. Conclusion

Beyond doubt, cognitive work based on metaphorical linguistic expressions has opened up the study of language to new areas of research. Most importantly, it paved the way to studies of experiential and cultural motivation for patterns of metaphorical thought, thereby establishing a close link of linguistics with two other disciplines--cognitive psychology and anthropology. Its undeniable success and its contribution to the linguistic field notwithstanding, the cognitive theory of metaphor has not confronted various criticisms it has been subject to with sufficient care and attention.

Seen in this light, this paper was meant to resume the discussion of the conceptual nature of metaphor. Its main aim was to show that there is a great diversity of linguistic evidence for patterns of metaphorical thought. This diversity, however, even though it speaks very strongly for the idea that metaphor is conceptual in nature, is not sufficient to justify it. Therefore, recognizing the fact that claims about our conceptual system which are based on linguistic analyses alone remain within the "language--thought--language" circle, the paper discussed also some kinds of nonlinguistic evidence for conceptual metaphors.

Psycholinguistic research on metaphorical reasoning has been one major source of such nonlinguistic verifications. As I tried to show on the basis of a sample of my study of the LIFE IS MUSIC metaphor, convergent evidence from language and music, may also serve to break open the "language--thought--language" circle.

To close up, let me put linguistic debates aside and, returning to the motto to this paper, give its original context provided by Langacker, who says:

Metaphorical thinking being unavoidable, we might as well relax and enjoy it. It is more helpful than harmful so long as we are aware that it is in fact metaphorical and are cognizant of its limitations. Ideally, it should be used to build up an apprehension of the target phenomenon which stands independently of any particular metaphor employed. Still any metaphor is misleading to some extent (2006: 108).

doi: 10.2478/v10121-009-0017-2

REFERENCES

PRIMARY SOURCES

CALD 2008 Cambridge Advanced learner's dictionary The Advanced Learner's Dictionary by A.S. Hornby started life as the Idiomatic and Syntactic Dictionary, published by Kaitakusha in Japan in 1942. It then made a perilous journey in wartime conditions to Britain and came under the wing of the Oxford University Press, which . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Cambridge University Press (known colloquially as CUP) is a publisher given a Royal Charter by Henry VIII in 1534, and one of the two privileged presses (the other being Oxford University Press). .

L-1 "In the beginning was sound", Lecture by Daniel Barenboim at Cadogan Hall Cadogan Hall is a 900-seat concert hall in Chelsea, London, in the United Kingdom. Its resident orchestra is the Royal Philharmonic Orchestra.

Previously, the building was the First Church of Christ, Scientist completed in 1907.
, London, BBC Radio, lecture audio and transcript of Reith lectures 2006, available at http://www.bbc.co.uk/radio4/reith2006/lecturel.shtml (date of access: 10 June 2006).

LD- Discussion after L 1.

L-3 "The magic of music", Lecture by Daniel Barenboim at the Berlin State Opera, BBC Radio, lecture audio and transcript of Reith Lectures 2006, available at http://www.bbc.co.uk/radio4/reith2006/lecture3.shtml (date of access: 10 June 2006).

MED 2002 Macmillan English dictionary for advanced learners. (1st edition.) 2002. Oxford: Macmillan Publishers Macmillan Publishers Ltd, also known as The Macmillan Group, is a privately-held international publishing company owned by Georg von Holtzbrinck Publishing Group. It has offices in 41 countries worldwide and operates in more than thirty others.  Limited.

SECONDARY SOURCES

Allwood, Jens 2003 "Meaning potential and context: Some consequences for the analysis of variation in meaning", in: Hubert Cuyckens-Rene Dirven-John R. Taylor (eds.), 29-65.

Barcelona, Antonio (ed.)

2000 Metaphor and metonymy at the crossroads. A cognitive perspective. (Topics in English linguistics 30.) Berlin: Mouton mouton

lamb pelt made to resemble seal or beaver.
 de Gruyter.

Brinton, Laurel J.-Elizabeth Closs Traugott 2005 Lexicalization and language change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Contini-Morava, Elen-Robert S. Kirsner-Betsy Rodriguez-Bachiller (eds.)

2004 Cognitive and communicative approaches to linguistic analysis'. (Studies in functional and structural linguistics structural linguistics
n. (used with a sing. verb)
1. A method of synchronic linguistic analysis employing structuralism, especially in contrasting those formal structures, such as phonemes or sentences, that make up systems, such as
 51 .) Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Cuyckens, Hubert-Rene Dirven-John R. Taylor (eds.)

2003 Cognitive approaches to lexical semantics. (Cognitive linguistics research 23.) Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

Damsio, Antonio 1999 The feeling of what happens." Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. New York New York, state, United States
New York, Middle Atlantic state of the United States. It is bordered by Vermont, Massachusetts, Connecticut, and the Atlantic Ocean (E), New Jersey and Pennsylvania (S), Lakes Erie and Ontario and the Canadian province of
: Harcourt Brace &Co.

2003 Looking for Spinoza." Joy, sorrow, and the feeling brain. New York: Harcourt Brace & Co.

Evans, Vyvyen 2004 The structure of time. Language, meaning and temporal cognition. (Human cognitive processing 12.) Amsterdam: Benjamins.

2006 "Lexical concepts, cognitive models and meaning construction", Cognitive Linguistics 17: 491-534.

Filipovic, Luna 2007 Talking about motion. A crosslinguistic investigation of lexicalization patterns. (Studies in language companion series 91.) Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Freeman, Margaret H.

2000 "Poetry and scope of metaphor: Toward a cognitive theory of literature", in: Antonio Barcelona (ed.), 250-281.

Gibbs, Raymond W.

1994 The poetics of mind. Figurative fig·u·ra·tive  
adj.
1.
a. Based on or making use of figures of speech; metaphorical: figurative language.

b. Containing many figures of speech; ornate.

2.
 thought, language, and understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

2005 "The psychological status of image schemas", in: Beate Hampe (ed.), 113-134.

in press "Walking the talk while thinking about the talk: Embodied interpretation of metaphorical narratives".

Gibbs, Raymond W. (ed.)

2008 The Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Gibbs, Raymond W.-Marcus Perlman 2006 "The contested impact of cognitive linguistic research on the psycholinguistics psycholinguistics, the study of psychological states and mental activity associated with the use of language. An important focus of psycholinguistics is the largely unconscious application of grammatical rules that enable people to produce and comprehend intelligible  of metaphor understanding", in: Gitte Kristiansen-Michael Achard-Rene Dirven Francisco J. Ruiz de Mendoza Ibanez (eds.), 211-228.

Raymond W. Gibbs-Gerard J. Steen (eds.)

1999 Metaphor in cognitive linguistics. Selected papers from the 5th International Cognitive Linguistics Conference, Amsterdam, 1997. (Current issues in linguistic theory 175.) Amsterdam: Benjamins.

Giora, Rachel 2003 On our mind. Salience sa·li·ence   also sa·li·en·cy
n. pl. sa·li·en·ces also sa·li·en·cies
1. The quality or condition of being salient.

2. A pronounced feature or part; a highlight.

Noun 1.
, context, and figurative language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Gorska, Elzbieta 2008 "Four arguments for patterns of metaphorical thought", Acta Philologica 34:5-31.

forthcom. "LIFE IS MUSIC--a case study of creative metaphorical thought".

Gorska, Elzbieta Gunter Radden (eds.)

2005 Metonymy-metaphor collage collage (kəläzh`, kō–) [Fr.,=pasting], technique in art consisting of cutting and pasting natural or manufactured materials to a painted or unpainted surface—hence, a work of art in this medium. . Warszawa: Warsaw University Press.

Grady, Joseph E.

2005 "'Image schemas and perception: Refining a definition", in: Beate Hampe (ed.), 35-55.

Hampe, Beate (ed.)

2005 From perception to meaning. (Cognitive linguistics research 29.) Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

Heine, Bernd 1997 Cognitive foundations of grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Heine, Bernd-Ulrike Claudi-Friederike Hunnemeyer 1991 Grammaticalization. A conceptual framework For the concept in aesthetics and art criticism, see .

A conceptual framework is used in research to outline possible courses of action or to present a preferred approach to a system analysis project.
. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press The University of Chicago Press is the largest university press in the United States. It is operated by the University of Chicago and publishes a wide variety of academic titles, including The Chicago Manual of Style, dozens of academic journals, including .

Heine, Bernd-Tania Kuteva 2002 World lexicon of grammaticalization. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Jakel, Olaf 1999 "Kant, Blumenberg, Weinreich: Some forgotten contributions to the cognitive theory of metaphor', in: Raymond W. Gibbs-Gerard J. Steen (eds.), 9-27.

Johnson, Mark 1987 The body in the mind: The bodily basis of imagination, reason, and meaning. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

2005 "The philosophical significance of image schemas", in: Beate Hampe (ed.), 15-33.

Keysar, Boaz-Shen Yeshayahu-Sam Gluckensberg-William S. Horton 2000 "Conventional language: How metaphoric is it?", Journal of Memory and Language 43: 576-593.

Koenig, Jean-Pierre (ed.)

1998 Discourse and cognition: Bridging the gap. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language of Information (CSLI CSLI Center for the Study of Language and Information
CSLI Civil Society and Local Initiatives
) Publications.

Kovecses, Zoltan 2002 Metaphor. A practical introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

2005 Metaphor in culture. Universality and variation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

2008 "Conceptual metaphor theory. Some criticisms and alternative proposals", Annual Review of Cognitive Linguistics 6:168-184.

Kristiansen, Gitte-Michael Achard-Rene Dirven-Francisco J. Ruiz de Mendoza Ibanez (eds.)

2006 Cognitive linguistics: Current applications and future perspective. (Applications of Cognitive linguistics 1.) Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

Krzeszowski, Tomasz P.

1988 "Wstep do wydania polskiego" [An introduction to the Polish edition], in: George Lakoff--Mark Johnson, 5-18.

Lakoff, George 1993 "The contemporary theory of metaphor", in: Andrew Ortony (ed.), 202-251.

Lakoff, George--Mark Johnson 1980 Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

1988 Metafory w naszym zyciu [Metaphors we live by]. (Translated by Tomasz P. Krzeszowski.) Warszawa: Panstwowy Instytut Wydawniczy.

1999 Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

Lakoff, George--Mark Turner 1989 More than cool reason. A field guide to poetic metaphor. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Langacker, Ronald W. 1987 Foundations of cognitive grammar Cognitive grammar is an influential cognitive approach to language developed since 1976 by Ronald Langacker. Langacker develops the central ideas of cognitive grammar in his seminal, two-volume Foundations of cognitive grammar . Vol. 1: Theoretical prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Stanford University, at Stanford, Calif.; coeducational; chartered 1885, opened 1891 as Leland Stanford Junior Univ. (still the legal name). The original campus was designed by Frederick Law Olmsted. David Starr Jordan was its first president.  Press.

1998 "On subjectification and grammaticalization", in: Jean-Pierre Koenig (ed.), 71-89.

2004 "Form, meaning, and behavior: The cognitive grammar analysis of double subject constructions", in: Elen Contini-Morava--Robert S. Kirsner--Betsy Rodriguez-Bachiller (eds.), 21-60.

2006 "On the continuous debate about discreteness", Cognitive Linguistics 17:107-151.

2008 Cognitive grammar. A basic introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ortony, Andrew (ed.)

1979 Metaphor and thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

1993 Metaphor and thought. (2nd edition.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ozagaliskan, Seyda

2005 "Metaphor meets typology typology /ty·pol·o·gy/ (ti-pol´ah-je) the study of types; the science of classifying, as bacteria according to type.

typology

the study of types; the science of classifying, as bacteria according to type.
: Ways of moving metaphorically in English and Turkish", Cognitive Linguistics 16: 207-256.

Reddy, Michael J. 1979 "The conduit metaphor--A case of frame conflict in our language about language", in: Andrew Ortony (ed.), 284-324.

Shopen, Tim (ed.) 1985 Language typology and syntactic description. Vol. 3: Grammatical categories and the lexicon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Slobin, Dan I. 2004 "The many ways to search for a frog: Linguistic typology linguistic typology
the classification of languages by structural similarity, e.g., similarity of syntactic or phonemic features, as opposed to classification on the basis of shared linguistic ancestry.
See also: Linguistics
 and expression of motion events", in: Sven Stromqvist--Ludo Vehoven (eds.), 219-257.

Stromqvist, Sven--Ludo Vehoven (eds.) 2004 Relating events in narrative. Vol. 2: Typological and contextual perspective. Mahvah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

Talmy, Leonard 1985 "Lexicalization patterns: Semantic structure in lexical form", in: Tim Shopen (ed.), 57-149.

Turner, Mark 1987 Death is the mother of beauty: Mind, metaphor, criticism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

1996 The literary mind Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Tyler, Andrea--Vyvyan Evans 2003 The semantics of English prepositions This is a list of English prepositions. In English, some prepositions are short, typically containing five letters or fewer. There are, however, a significant number of multi-word prepositions. . Spatial scenes, embodied meaning and cognition. Cambridge--New York: Cambridge University Press.

Zbikowski, Lawrence M. 2008 "Metaphor and music", in: Raymond W. Gibbs (ed.), 502-523.

Zlatev, Jordan 2003 "Polysemy or generality'? Mu", in: Hubert Cuyckens--Rene Dirven--John R. Taylor (eds.), 447-494.

INTERNET SOURCES

Barsalou, Lawrence W. 2008 "Grounded cognition", Annual Review of Psychology 59: 617-645, available at http://psychology.emory.edu/cognition/barsalou/papers/Barsalou_ARP_2008_ground ed_cognition.pdf, (date of access: 8 June 2009).

2009 "Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction", Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society The Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, or Phil. Trans., is a scientific journal published by the Royal Society.

Begun in 1665, it is the oldest scientific journal printed in the English-speaking world and the second oldest in the world,
 of London." Biological Sciences 364: 1281-1289, available at http://psychology.emory.edu/cognition/barsalou/onlinepapers.html (date of access: 29 June 2009).

(11) See, in particular, Gibbs-Perlman (2006) and the literature cited therein.

(12) For a more elaborate formulation of this approach, called the theory of lexical concepts and cognitive models, see Evans (2006).

(13) For overviews see, for example, Kovecses (2002) and Gibbs (2008); see also Gorska (2008).

(14) The greatest discrepancy is in the number of participants who selected the smooth journey story as their answer to Question (iv) (of. 60% in Gibbs's study and 90% in my study). This difference seems to suggest that for the Polish participants a romantic relationship is very likely to succeed if there are no obstacles on its way so that nothing prolongs its smooth development (i.e. when it may proceed along a straight line), and in the case of American participants this factor has a much lower effect.

(16) An earlier version of this study is also discussed in Gibbs (2005: 129-130); for more on the role of simulation (i.e. re-enactment of perceptual, motor and introspective in·tro·spect  
intr.v. in·tro·spect·ed, in·tro·spect·ing, in·tro·spects
To engage in introspection.



[Latin intr
 states acquired during experience with the world, body and mind) in cognition see Barsalou (2008, 2009).

(17) See also Gorska (forthcoming).

(18) An inquisitive in·quis·i·tive  
adj.
1. Inclined to investigate; eager for knowledge.

2. Unduly curious and inquiring. See Synonyms at curious.
 reader is invited to visit the BBC Reith lectures archives (see the Data sources below). It is highly likely that Barenboim's musical "argument" would bring about a similar reaction of the reader.

(19) For a recent overview of research on metaphor and music see Zbikowski 2008 and the literature cited therein. For the present purpose, suffice it to observe that, so far, the research has concentrated on three issues: (i) metaphorical language about music; (ii) metaphor in the "language" of music, and of music theory in particular; (iii) the correlation between text and accompanying music (as in songs).

ELZBIETA GORSKA

University of Warsaw History
1816-31
The Royal University of Warsaw was established in 1816, when the partitions of Poland separated Warsaw from the oldest and most influential Polish academic center, in Kraków.
 
COPYRIGHT 2009 Adam Mickiewicz University
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2009 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 Reader Opinion

Title:

Comment:



 

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Gorska, Elzbieta
Publication:Studia Anglica Posnaniensia: international review of English Studies
Date:Jul 1, 2009
Words:10117
Previous Article:Nonstandard were and the nonstandard forms of the preterite negative of to be in nineteenth century new England civil war letters and literary...
Next Article:Natural syntax of Belfast English (i) subject-verb agreement, (ii) imperative.
Topics:

Terms of use | Copyright © 2014 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters