Printer Friendly
The Free Library
22,719,120 articles and books

Federalism, Subnational Constitutions, and Minority Rights.



G. Alan Tarr, Robert F. Williams

For other people named Robert Williams, see Robert Williams (disambiguation).
Robert Franklin Williams (February 26, 1925 – October 15, 1996) was a civil rights leader, author, and the president of the Monroe, North Carolina NAACP chapter in
, and Josef Marko, eds., Federalism federalism.

1 In political science, see federal government.

2 In U.S. history, see states' rights.
federalism

Political system that binds a group of states into a larger, noncentralized, superior state while allowing them
, Subnational Constitutions, and Minority Rights (Westport, Conn.: Praeger, 2004). Pp. viii, 247.

A book devoted to an analysis of "how federalism and subnational constitutions have served to safeguard the rights of minorities ... [and] of the conditions under which they are likely to do so" (vii-viii) is a rarity deserving of attention. Professor Tarr and his collaborators have produced a book well worth reading.

Part I provides an overview of some "horizontal" issues involved in subnational constitutionalism con·sti·tu·tion·al·ism  
n.
1. Government in which power is distributed and limited by a system of laws that must be obeyed by the rulers.

2.
a. A constitutional system of government.

b.
 in federal states. The next three parts are devoted to case studies of countries, divided between "mature federal systems": Austria, Germany, and the United States of America UNITED STATES OF AMERICA. The name of this country. The United States, now thirty-one in number, are Alabama, Arkansas, Connecticut, Delaware, Florida, Georgia, Illinois, Indiana, Iowa, Kentucky, Louisiana, Maine, Maryland, Massachusetts, Michigan, Mississippi, Missouri, New Hampshire,  (Part II); "regional systems in transformation": Italy and Spain (Part III); and "multinational federations": Belgium, Bosnia and Herzegovina Bosnia and Herzegovina (bŏz`nēə, hĕrtsəgōvē`nə), Serbo-Croatian Bosna i Hercegovina, country (2005 est. pop. 4,025,000), 19,741 sq mi (51,129 sq km), on the Balkan peninsula, S Europe. , India, and Switzerland (Part IV).

To examine all twelve essays in detail is not possible here. And so, after pointing to some of the deficiencies of this work, my aim will be to emphasize some of the ideas it contains that are particularly worthy of attention for a Canadian audience, especially for those scholars interested in Aboriginal legal issues.

Professors Williams and Tarr's introductory essay (Robert E Williams & G Alan Tarr, "Subnational Constitutional Space: A View from the States, Provinces, Regions, Lander, and Cantons" 3) examines, from a comparative law perspective, the question of how subnational entities are recognized (or tolerated) in national constitutions or constitutional space. They first rightfully underline underline

an animal's ventral profile; the shape of the belly when viewed from the side, e.g. pendulous, pot-belly, tucked up, gaunt.
 that a subnational perspective allows for a study of constitutional federalism that is not obsessed by the sole examination of the national constitution's provisions nor by the univocal perspective of the national government. It also enables one to envisage en·vis·age  
tr.v. en·vis·aged, en·vis·ag·ing, en·vis·ag·es
1. To conceive an image or a picture of, especially as a future possibility: envisaged a world at peace.

2.
 "the relationship of national and subnational constitutions in federal systems as interdependent [rather than hierarchical]" (4). With that in mind, the authors then analyze issues such as: "the amount of subnational constitutional space, competency, or autonomy that the component units are allotted al·lot  
tr.v. al·lot·ted, al·lot·ting, al·lots
1. To parcel out; distribute or apportion: allotting land to homesteaders; allot blame.

2.
 within the federal system" (6); the policing of the outer limits of subnational constitution making (whether the federal constitution invests the central government with some control over the content of subnational constitutions, whether such control should be exercised by a constitutional court, or whether the national constitution should prescribe the contents of subnational constitutions); the manner in which different subnational entities have exercised their constitutional powers and the reasons for the differences among subnational constitutions. The authors then enumerate To count or list one by one. For example, an enumerated data type defines a list of all possible values for a variable, and no other value can then be placed into it. See device enumeration and ENUM.  a number of questions that could be pursued usefully in studying subnational constitutions. In their conclusion, Williams and Tarr note that "subnational units in federal systems more often underutilize their constitution-making competency than they overutilize it" (15). They lament this underutilization because in an era of "reawakening reawakening ndespertar m

reawakening nréveil m

reawakening nWiedererwachen nt
 of political awareness and regional identity ... the allocation of power to subnational units, including the power to determine their own constitutional arrangements, might provide a form of self-determination that can serve as an alternative to illegal movements for secession" (ibid.) and "may also be crucial for minorities, who might find it easier to gain recognition of their rights at the subnational constitutional level" (15-16).

One problem with the authors' approach has to do with their definition of "constitution", one that seems confirmed to a formal rather than a material understanding of the concept of constitution. The reader is left with the impression that the case studies that follow only provide an in-depth examination of subnational formal constitutional provisions as opposed to subnational material constitutional provisions. (5) This is definitely not the case since most of the contributors insist on the protection provided by both formal and informal subnational constitutions.

Two essays also seem to fit awkwardly within the general theme. The Spanish contribution (Eduardo J. Ruiz Vieytez, "Federalism, Subnational Constitutional Arrangements, and the Protection of Minorities in Spain" 133) has next to nothing to say about the protection afforded by this country's subnational constitutions, (6) as it only deals with those provided by the national constitution. Furthermore, Kristin Henrard's essay dealing with the equality principle ("Equality Considerations and Their Relation to Minority Protections, State Constitutional Law, and Federalism" 25)--although interesting--is mostly concerned with a general discussion of the concept, leaving aside its particular application in the context of subnational constitutions. (7)

Although all of the essays are worth reading, some do stand out, especially those that tackle the definition of the word "minority". For instance, Francesco Palermo's essay "Asymmetric A difference between two opposing modes. It typically refers to a speed disparity. For example, in asymmetric operations, it takes longer to compress and encrypt data than to decompress and decrypt it. Contrast with symmetric. See asymmetric compression and public key cryptography. , 'Quasi-Federal' Regionalism re·gion·al·ism  
n.
1.
a. Political division of an area into partially autonomous regions.

b. Advocacy of such a political system.

2. Loyalty to the interests of a particular region.

3.
 and the Protection of Minorities: The Case of Italy" (107) underlines that, in a federation, the notion of minority is a variable one. He accurately insists on the fact that "[m]inorities, as such, do not exist" (122 [footnotes omitted]). (8) Rather, "[t]hey only become relevant in relationship to other groups having a dominant position ..." (ibid.). As he underlines, "[o]ne could ... argue that groups of people become minorities inasmuch as in·as·much as  
conj.
1. Because of the fact that; since.

2. To the extent that; insofar as.


inasmuch as
conj

1. since; because

2.
 they are disadvantaged in the decision-making process at a certain level of governance. Thus, the concept of minority will probably become a variable one, depending on the level of government involved" (ibid. [footnotes omitted]).

Jens Woelk's essay entitled "Federalism and Consociationalism Consociationalism is a form of government involving guaranteed group representation, and is often suggested for managing conflict in deeply divided societies.

Consociationalism was discussed in academic terms by the political scientist Arend Lijphart.
 as Tools for State Reconstruction? The Case of Bosnia and Herzegovina" (177) underlines the need, in certain circumstances, to differentiate the notion of minority with that of "constituent peoples". It deals with situations "where the term 'minorities' cannot be applied, in a technical sense, to the main constituent groups [of a country]" (179 [footnotes omitted]). For example, in recognition of the fact that Bosniaks, Serbs, and Croats are not simply minorities in the Republic of Bosnia and Herzegovina, that state's constitution recognizes their status as "Constituent Peoples". Such distinction has lead the Supreme Court of that country to conclude, in the words of Woelk, that:
   [t]he Entities thus have a constitutional obligation not to
   discriminate against those constituent peoples of the state who are
   as a matter of fact a numerical minority within their territory
   (i.e., Serbs in the Federation, Bosniaks and Croats in the
   Republika Srpska). The principle of nondiscrimination thus applies
   not only to individuals, but also to groups as such, prohibiting
   special adverse treatment. For the Court, a principle of
   "collective equality" of the constituent peoples exists that
   "prohibits any special privilege for one or two of these peoples,
   any domination in governmental structures or any ethnic
   homogenization through segregation based on territorial separation"
   (188-189 [references omitted]).


In "A Dynamic Federalism Built on Static Principles: The Case of Belgium" (157), Wouter Pas addresses the same distinction, although he does not speak specifically of constituent peoples. This interesting distinction between minorities and constituent peoples bears a lot of similarities to Will Kymlicka's distinction between "ethnic groups" and "national minorities". (9) For Canadian scholars interested in accommodating Quebecois and Aboriginal nationalisms, such distinction merits closer examination.

Another series of essays, while emphasizing federalism's capacity to promote the collective equality of groups, stress that federalism also aims at promoting the democratic integration of these groups within the overall state. In addition, these essays emphasize that federalism should be conceived of as a power-sharing exercise and not just a mask for subnational majoritarian ma·jor·i·tar·i·an  
adj.
Based on majority rule: "a naively uncomplicated premise of simple majoritarian democracy" Saturday Review.

n.
An advocate of majoritarianism.
 leadership. In what I believe to be the most interesting of all the essays, "Participation in the Decision-Making Process as a Means of Group Accommodation" (41), Nicole Topperwien examines how local minorities in culturally heterogeneous subnational states can be integrated politically through participation rights. Such integration in the decision-making process, she argues, might "enhance the loyalty to and identification with the state and prevents the alienation inherent in the feeling of being a perennial loser" (42 [footnotes omitted]). After an interesting discussion of who should be allowed to exercise participatory rights, and an examination of the particular nature of these rights, Topperwien underlines the danger of putting too much emphasis on the rights of groups:
   When all institutions are constituted so as to represent the groups
   and there is not a counterweighing representation of the citizenry
   as a whole, there can as well only be direct legitimacy of
   decisions in respect to the groups. In such a case, state
   legitimacy derives from and depends on group legitimacies. Disputes
   between groups can put the state as such in question because the
   state does not have legitimacy on its own to justify its existence
   and thus has no basis through which it could counterweigh, bridge,
   or mediate conflicts. Though participation rights aim at
   ameliorating legitimacy of groups, this must not be done in
   detriment to an overall legitimacy (47 [footnotes omitted]).


The author then concludes that "[i]n the end, only participation fights that find the acceptance of all concerned groups and that are not in opposition to an overall or overarching o·ver·arch·ing  
adj.
1. Forming an arch overhead or above: overarching branches.

2. Extending over or throughout: "I am not sure whether the missing ingredient . . .
 legitimacy will have chances of being effective" (48). Readers familiar with Alan C. Cairns' thesis in Citizens Plus: Aboriginal Peoples and the Canadian State (10) will find Professor Topperwien's essay particularly illuminating.

Finally, in an essay entitled "Federalism and Nonterritorial Minorities in India" (199), Arshi Khan underlines the dangers inherent in the implementation of federalism in a nonliberal community such as India, where "religion has become the fundamental basis of identification for the individual and group ..." (205). In such a context, federalism must
   not only [serve] to allocate power among governing institutions but
   also to encourage a commitment to the interests and well-being of
   all segments of society. On the one hand, federalism empowers
   subnational units within their specified area of influence. On the
   other, it may be reasonable to limit the powers and autonomy of
   these units in order to safeguard the well-being of all the people
   ... (208).


In other words Adv. 1. in other words - otherwise stated; "in other words, we are broke"
put differently
, federalism should be concerned with the sharing of power and not simply with the division of power:
   [Federalism] can ... serve as the impetus for considering all
   viable mechanisms, be they minority rights, regionalism,
   consociationalism, proportional representation, or other steps,
   that can ensure power sharing. Without such a concern, federalism
   would only serve the cosmetic purpose of division of powers and not
   sharing of powers. In the case of India, a full commitment to this
   understanding of federalism would mean that both the Union and state
   governments would create mechanisms to protect minorities not only
   from threats of violence but also from majoritarianism. Otherwise,
   the federal arrangements would be merely a constitutional mask for
   the majoritarian leadership in the Union and the states to violate
   the rights of minorities (209).


Again, this essay provides food for thought for those who examine the question of the protection of individual rights within autonomous Aboriginal political entities.

Jean Leclair

(5) For instance, they insist on the fact that, in Canada, there are no "subnational constitutions independent of the federal constitution" (5) and that this country has shown that "federal systems can get along quite well without subnational constitutions" (10). There might not be any provincial constitutions in the formal sense, but many legal rules (common law, constitutional conventions, and statute law) would qualify as constitutional in a material sense. For example, provincial human fights codes, defined as quasi-constitutional documents, certainly play an important role in the protection of human rights in Canada.

(6) With the exception of the second to last paragraph of the essay (150).

(7) With the exception of the following conclusion: "[T]he prohibition of discrimination does not stand in the way of subnational units adopting constitutions that have their own additional measures pertaining per·tain  
intr.v. per·tained, per·tain·ing, per·tains
1. To have reference; relate: evidence that pertains to the accident.

2.
 to human rights and minority protection ..." (35). See also 30.

(8) Sec also 130, n. 68.

(9) Will Kymlicka Will Kymlicka is a Canadian political philosopher. He is currently Professor of Philosophy and Canada Research Chair (Tier 1) in Political Philosophy at Queen's University, and Recurrent Visiting Professor in the Nationalism Studies Program at the Central European University in , Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).

(9) Will Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).

(10) (Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press The University of British Columbia Press is a university press that is part of the University of British Columbia. It was established in 1971. External links
  • University of British Columbia Press
, 2000).
COPYRIGHT 2006 McGill Law Journal (Canada)
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2006 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 Reader Opinion

Title:

Comment:



 

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Leclair, Jean
Publication:McGill Law Journal
Article Type:Book review
Date:Mar 22, 2006
Words:1940
Previous Article:The American Choice-of-Law Revolution in the Courts: Today and Tomorrow.
Next Article:Domesticating the exotic species: international biodiversity law in Canada.
Topics:

Terms of use | Copyright © 2014 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters