Printer Friendly

Anger and community in the knight's tale.

As Chaucer's Wife of Bath comes to the end of her life story and prepares to tell her tale, the Friar interrupts her, commenting on the considerable length of her prologue: "This is a long preamble of a tale" (831). (1) The Friar laughs as he says this and it is not clear that the Wife is bothered in any way; but before she can respond, the Summoner accuses the Friar of interfering and of taking the fun out of the tale-telling game ("Thou lettest our disport dis·port  
v. dis·port·ed, dis·port·ing, dis·ports

v.intr.
To amuse oneself in a light, frolicsome manner.

v.tr.
1. To amuse (oneself) in a light, frolicsome manner.

2.
" [839]). The Friar then promises to tell a tale (or two) about summoners which will make the whole company laugh. Cursing the Friar, the Summoner in turn vows two (or three) tales which will wound the Friar ("make thyn herte for to morne" [848]). Before either the Friar or the Summoner can begin a tale, however, the Host intervenes. He allows the Wife to continue and momentarily restores order, though the conflict between the Friar and Summoner surfaces again later in their respective tales. This angry quarrel between the Friar and Summoner exposes the tensions and anxieties inherent in medieval social relations, though Chaucer's characterization of the two men as vengeful storytellers directs our attention largely to the private, or personal, dimension of the Friar's and Summoner's mutual anger. Thanks to the Host's management of the interruption at the end of the Wife's prologue, the Friar's and Summoner's hatred of one another has relatively little impact on the pilgrim fellowship or on the tale-telling game itself. In the Knight's Tale, by contrast, Chaucer provides a perspective on the consequences of an individual's anger for the community at large. This essay examines the course of Theseus' various angers in order to explore Chaucer's interest in the way in which human anger contributes to both the order and disorder Order and Disorder
See also classification.

agenda

things to be done or a list of those things, as a list of the matters to be discussed at a meeting.

anarchy

extreme disorder. See also government.
 of human fellowships. I argue that the tale, read as a tale of anger rather than (as is often the case) a tale of pity, reveals Chaucer's preoccupation with the problem of anger and his ambivalent evaluation of its dual nature, at once a necessary and a destructive force in human affairs. In contrast to scholastic writings on anger, Chaucer's tale imagines an anger both less easy to control and more desirable to encourage than scholastic thinkers tend to suggest.

Because anger is not traditionally regarded as a Chaucerian topic or as an organizing principle for the Canterbury project as whole, critical attention has focused largely on either the negative consequences of anger or on the virtue of patience exhibited in the tales. Indeed, if we add Griselda and Custance to the list of patient and merciful mer·ci·ful  
adj.
Full of mercy; compassionate: sought merciful treatment for the captives. See Synonyms at humane.



mer
 figures featuring Emelye, Prudence, and Mary, we have the core of what Jill Mann persuasively argues is the ethical ideal of pietas Pietas

goddess of faithfulness, respect, and affection. [Rom. Myth.: Kravitz, 192]

See : Faithfulness
 at the heart of Chaucer's work:

[T]he Canterbury Tales, for all its rich variety of mode and genre, contains not a single example of the story-type that embodies its ideals in the central figure of a male hero. Instead, the tales that mediate serious ideals are focused on a series of women: Constance, Griselda, Prudence, Cecilia. The male hero enters only in the burlesque burlesque (bûrlĕsk`) [Ital.,=mockery], form of entertainment differing from comedy or farce in that it achieves its effects through caricature, ridicule, and distortion. It differs from satire in that it is devoid of any ethical element.  form of Sir Thopas, to be unceremoniously bundled out of the way in favour of the tale that celebrates the idealized i·de·al·ize  
v. i·de·al·ized, i·de·al·iz·ing, i·de·al·iz·es

v.tr.
1. To regard as ideal.

2. To make or envision as ideal.

v.intr.
1.
 wisdom of a woman, Chaucer's tale of Melibee. (Feminizing Chaucer 3)

One might argue that Theseus, outside the "feminine" virtues he exhibits, represents a "masculine" political ideal in the Knight's Tale, and my discussion of the tale will suggest that there is a positive as well as negative dimension to his anger. But I am less interested in the debate occasioned by Mann's work regarding Chaucer's attitude toward gender, than in the implication our reading of Chaucer's female characters has for our understanding of his attitude toward anger. (2)

For all his reservations about the way in which people like the Friar justify their actions by aligning themselves with God's divine anger, Chaucer also recognized anger as a necessary and inevitable principle. While it is true that in the tales of anger and society such as the Knight's Tale or the Tale of Melibee Chaucer generally depicts anger as undesirable, he takes pains to underscore The underscore character (_) is often used to make file, field and variable names more readable when blank spaces are not allowed. For example, NOVEL_1A.DOC, FIRST_NAME and Start_Routine.

(character) underscore - _, ASCII 95.
 its inevitability, at least in the human world. My reading of Theseus, then, does not challenge the notion of Chaucer's feminine ideal (or of his hope that this will reinvent re·in·vent  
tr.v. re·in·vent·ed, re·in·vent·ing, re·in·vents
1. To make over completely: "She reinvented Indian cooking to fit a Western kitchen and a Western larder" 
 the masculine ideal), as much as expand our understanding of the context in which these ideals function. Chaucerian ideals of patience and mercy exist against the backdrop of an angry world, but not just as solutions or reme dies for anger. The relation is more subtle because Chaucer's text is aware of the potential failure of such ideals, outside of an exemplary narrative, to conquer the anger they respond to. Chaucer's tales beg the question Beg the Question is a graphic novel by Bob Fingerman. It chronicles the trials and tribulations of protagonists Rob — a squeamish freelance cartoonist/pornographer — and Sylvia — a beauty salon manager with loftier aspirations — as well as a  of whether, despite being ideals, they are desirable. They ask us to consider whether a world without anger is a state in which the human imagination can be entirely comfortable.

It is for this reason that anger rises to the level of a Chaucerian subject in its own right and is, I believe, a central principle governing the Canterbury project as a whole. This is not to suggest that it functions in the same organizational way as the topic of patience or pity. But if pietas is the deliberate thematic strand running through the work, anger is an irrepressible preoccupation of Chaucer's shadowing that strand.

The center of a preoccupation is, structurally speaking, difficult to identify. It is not clear that the tales or any subgroup of tales was intentionally organized around the topic of anger. There is no "anger group" equivalent to the much discussed "marriage group." While the issue of divine anger is not exclusive to the Friar's Tale, the story of the summoner's road to hell is a focal point focal point
n.
See focus.
 for analysis. The focus for a discussion of anger and society is less clear. Though Prudence's endeavor to restrain Melibee's desire for revenge stands out--not least because it is told by the pilgrim Chaucer--its analysis of anger can only be privileged to a point. Melibee seems more in keeping with Chaucer's overall ethical perspective and emphasis on patience, but the tale is not an end in itself any more than, say, the Knight's Tale. Because the Canterbury project's treatment of anger resists having a center, the Tales become a meditation on the problem rather than a treatise, a narrative thought experiment rather than an organized lesson on anger for its audience. This essay considers the Knight's Tale and its concern over the consequences of an individual's anger for his community, but does not assume one tale rewrites another or should be--ethically speaking--privileged over another.

I. The Anger of the "gentil duc": The Ambivalent Critical Reception of Chaucer's Theseus

No one in the pilgrim audience openly criticizes the Knight or the hero of his tale, though the narrator NARRATOR. A pleader who draws narrs serviens narrator, a sergeant at law. Fleta, 1. 2, c. 37. Obsolete.  observes that the "gentils" in particular praised the Knight's story. One suspects that Theseus may have been received less than favorably by some of the other pilgrims, and Lee Patterson Lee Patterson (born March 31, 1929 in Vancouver, British Columbia), is a Canadian television actor. Died February 14, 2007.

With roles on shows such as Surfside 6
 sees the Miller's Tale as a direct critique of Theseus and the Knight. (3) By modern critics, too, Theseus has been variously assessed. J. D. Burnley (26) and A. J. Minnis (8) identify in Theseus Chaucer's celebration of a virtuous pagan Virtuous paganism is a concept of Christian theology parallel to the Righteous Among the Nations in Judaism. It addressed the problem of pagans who were never evangelized and consequently during their lifetime had no opportunity to recognize Christ, but nevertheless led virtuous  and of a cautious, just administrator. For David Aers, however, the detailed account of the cost of Theseus' campaigns in blood and suffering suggests that "Chaucer's imagination had great sympathy with the growing criticism of war (the lust for conquest and its economic foundations) among late medieval writers" (176). (4) Responding to those readers uncomfortable with the ethics of Theseus' politics (and who question the extent to which Chaucer shared Theseus' or the Knight's sanguine sanguine /san·guine/ (sang´gwin)
1. plethoric.

2. ardent or hopeful.


san·guine
adj.
1. Of a healthy, reddish color; ruddy.

2.
 view of war), John Pratt For other persons named John Pratt, see John Pratt (disambiguation).

John William Pratt (October 22, 1894—December 1973) was a politician in Manitoba, Canada. He served in the Legislative Assembly of Manitoba from 1927 to 1936.
 defends Theseus' moral and political choices in light of what he argues would be Chaucer's late-medieval conception of a necessary and just war. (5)

Daniel Kempton describes Theseus' ambivalent critical reception as the product of two traditions: the French tradition (embodied in Muscatine's work) which sees the Knight's Tale as a celebration of the romantic-heroic values of chivalry chivalry (shĭv`əlrē), system of ethical ideals that arose from feudalism and had its highest development in the 12th and 13th cent. , with Theseus as the embodiment of those values; and the English tradition which views those values with skepticism, identifying in Theseus' order the potential for chaos (238). I think, however, the division among critics also has its origins in our uncertainty about how to value Theseus' private and public anger, not just his militarism Militarism
See also Soldiering.

Adrastus

leader of the Seven against Thebes. [Gk. Myth.: Iliad]

Siegfried

killed many enemies; led many troops to victory. [Ger. Lit. Nibelungenlied]
. In a sense, by focusing on the political and military aspects of the tale, modern readers undervalue Chaucer's careful portrayal of Theseus, the knights, and even Emelye, as angry individuals. By looking closely at the eruptions of Theseus' anger, I want to suggest that anger is an explicit concern of the tale. The issue for Chaucer is not just the violence of Theseus' policies or the consequences of militarism for Ricardian society, but the anger which shapes both public and private conduct.

To observe Chaucer's interest in anger as a moral and social, rather than specifically political, problem is to return to what might be thought of as a "traditional" reading of the Knight's Tale and the Tale of Melibee, by observing them as stories about moral behavior independent of the politics, if not the culture, of the period.6 It is to focus on the way in which Theseus's interaction with the other characters uncovers the qualities of mercy and generosity at the core of his ethical world view:

As he was ready to combat 'ire' and 'tirannye' in Creon, Theseus is ready to combat them in himself, and it is through his 'womanly' qualities that he conquers them.... Theseus's heroism consists not in his attempt to impose an ordered stasis stasis /sta·sis/ (sta´sis)
1. a stoppage or diminution of flow, as of blood or other body fluid.

2. a state of equilibrium among opposing forces.
 on the flux of existence, but rather in his readiness to move with the course of events, to match their change with his own. (Mann, Feminizing Chaucer 136-37)

In revisiting this concept of Theseus as the exemplar ex·em·plar  
n.
1. One that is worthy of imitation; a model. See Synonyms at ideal.

2. One that is typical or representative; an example.

3. An ideal that serves as a pattern; an archetype.

4.
 of pity, I want to rethink the place anger has in the tale, and to test the notion that anger is indeed "conquered" in the Knight's Tale. While I believe some readers (Aers, Olsson) exaggerate Theseus' faults, this first section of the essay questions the accuracy of the Knight's positive assessment of Theseus, not to denigrate den·i·grate  
tr.v. den·i·grat·ed, den·i·grat·ing, den·i·grates
1. To attack the character or reputation of; speak ill of; defame.

2.
 the duke's persisting anger, but to track and evaluate its practical, especially social, consequences. This is, in part, also to question how open to the effects of pity Theseus actually is. In reexamining the extent to which the "pitee" Theseus demonstrates is a remedy for his anger, we observe the extent to which Chaucer sees anger as a formidable challenge for even the virtue of pietas.

II. The Case for Theseus as Anger Management Specialist: The Ambiguous Success of the Amphitheater

The case for Theseus' victory over anger finds its best support in Theseus' response to the two knights dueling in the grove; and in his decision not to execute them for defying his authority, but to create an amphitheater in which their dispute can be settled by law:
   The queene anon, for verray wommanhede,
   Gan for to wepe, and so dide Emelye,
   And alle the ladyes in the compaignye....
   Til at the laste aslaked was his mood,
   For pitee renneth soone in gentil herte.
   And though he first for ire quook and sterte ...
   Yet in his reson he hem bothe excused. (1748-66)

   And forthy I yow putte in this degree,
   That ech of yow shal have his destynee
   As hym is shape, and herkneth in what wyse;
   Lo, heere youre ende of that I shal devyse....
   The lystes shal I maken in this place,
   And God so wisly on my soule rewe
   As I shal even juge been and trewe. (1841-64)


I would agree that, at first, it does seem that Theseus achieves a measure of success and asserts a degree of control, at least with respect to his own angry behavior. (7) Theseus draws strength from the community of people around him. The weeping of the queen captures Theseus' attention which, from his first angry outburst upon discovering the knights, had been focused on the knights and himself, on his authority and their death. The queen reorients Theseus to the rest of the community and initiates his thoughts about the nature of the knights' offense, the responsibilities of a prince, and how the community as a whole might deal with the situation in other ways. The group places limits on the individual's ability to indulge anger and desire for revenge, and in this case the presence of the women proves pivotal. And as Theseus' anger is contained by an exterior force (he is, as Mann says, "feminized" from without), so he attempts to work a similar change upon the two knights. The women bring public pressure to bear on Theseus and the amphitheater exerts a similar pressure. It does not "feminize fem·i·nize  
tr.v. fem·i·nized, fem·i·niz·ing, fem·i·niz·es
1. To give a feminine appearance or character to.

2. To cause (a male) to assume feminine characteristics.
" the knights, but does "civilize civ·i·lize  
tr.v. civ·i·lized, civ·i·liz·ing, civ·i·liz·es
1. To raise from barbarism to an enlightened stage of development; bring out of a primitive or savage state.

2.
" them in the narrow sense of forcing them to submit to Theseus' decree (representative of the will of the community) and to express their anger in a limited venue sanctioned by the community.

I would argue, however, that Theseus' victory over anger is something of an illusion, in part because the change of heart involves a change of plan that reconfigures anger into new yet equally destructive forms. Throughout the tales, Chaucer repeatedly underscores that while the social pressure of a community can be effective in containing anger, it also has limits. At the end of the Pardoner's Tale Pardoner’s Tale

three brothers kill each other for treasure. [Br. Lit.: Canterbury Tales, “Pardoner’s Tale”]

See : Greed
 we observe, for example, the way in which the Knight's intervention in the Host-Pardoner quarrel revisits this issue of anger and containment in a daily-life setting, outside the ideal romance setting that the Knight seems to take for granted in his own tale. For the moment, I will note that Theseus' strategy of containment also proves less than successful, and not just because the vagaries of fortune affect the tournament. Such "containment" of anger still involves a redirection of Theseus' own aggressive energies, an extension and an expansion of the feud between the two knights, and a sanctioning of a tournament the violence of which contributes to the death of Arcite, an event which invites an even more powerful and widespread anger. To the extent that Theseus' solution is really about the reassertion Re`as`ser´tion   

n. 1. A second or renewed assertion of the same thing.

Noun 1. reassertion - renewed affirmation
reaffirmation
 of power, his anger is not so much "rejected" (in Mann's phrase) as it is mollified when he dictates to others how the situation will be resolved in his own terms ("youre ende ... I shal devyse"; "the lystes shal ... I maken"; "I shal ... juge been"). The Queen's intervention in the Knight's Tale simply forces Theseus' aggression along a different path. (8)

This new path leads to the construction of the amphitheather, which is built upon the very space of the grove. It is as if Theseus attempts to reconfigure both the space and the angry emotions generated within that space by replacing them with his carefully designed theater. (9) However, Theseus' attempt to contain anger through the architecture of the amphitheater appears less successful than, say, that of his prototype, Boccaccio's Teseo. The images of anger inscribed in·scribe  
tr.v. in·scribed, in·scrib·ing, in·scribes
1.
a. To write, print, carve, or engrave (words or letters) on or in a surface.

b. To mark or engrave (a surface) with words or letters.
 on the walls of Theseus's amphitheater are telling:
   Ther saugh I first the derke ymaginyng
   Of Felonye, and al the compassyng;
   The crueel Ire, reed as any gleede;
   The pykepurs, and eek the pale Drede;
   The smylere with the knyf under the cloke;
   The shepne brennynge with the blake smoke;
   The tresoun of the mordrynge in the bedde;
   The open werre, with woundes al bibledde;
   Contek, with blody knyf and sharp manace.
   Al ful of chirkyng was that sory place.
   The sleere of hymself yet saugh I ther--
   His herte-blood hath bathed al his heer--
   The nayl ydryven in the shode anyght;
   The colde deeth, with mouth gapyng upright.
   Amyddes of the temple sat Meschaunce,
   With disconfort and sory contenaunce.
   Yet saugh I Woodnesse, laughynge in his rage,
   Armed Compleint, Outhees, and fiers Outrage;
   The careyne in the busk, with throte ycorve;
   A thousand slayn, and nat of qualm ystorve;
   The tiraunt, with the pray by force yraft;
   The toun destroyed, ther was no thyng laft.
   Yet saugh I brent the shippes hoppesteres;
   The hunte strangled with the wilde beres;
   The sowe freten the child right in the cradel;
   The cook yscalded, for al his long ladel.
   Noght was foryeten by the infortune of Marte.
   The cartere overryden with his carte--
   Under the wheel ful lowe he lay adoun.
   Ther were also, of Martes divisioun,
   The barbour, and the bocher, and the smyth,
   That forgeth sharpe swerdes on his stynth.
   And al above, depeynted in a tour,
   Saugh I Conquest, sittynge in greet honour,
   With sharpe swerd over his heed
   Hangynge by a soutil twynes threed.
   Depeynted was the slaughtre of Julius,
   Of grete Nero, and of Antonius.... (1995-2032)


Many of these images are present in Boccaccio's text as well. However, in Boccaccio's version, it is the personified prayer of Arcite which directly witnesses such images as it rises to heaven and visits the palace of Mars. In Chaucer's version, the portraits become a physical part of Theseus' architecture, reminders of the anger that filled the grove before the construction of the theater and prescient pre·scient  
adj.
1. Of or relating to prescience.

2. Possessing prescience.



[French, from Old French, from Latin praesci
 images of the violent emotions that will persist after the theater is torn down to make room for Arcite's funeral pyre. (10)

Compared to the images in Boccaccio's unworldly temple, the violent scenes in Chaucer's earthly temple are also more specific and depict in more detail the violence of the everyday human world. Where Boccaccio's images emphasize the suffering of the individual in time of war, Chaucer calls attention to the thief, the murderer, and the arsonist unconnected to acts of war Tom Clancy's Op-Center: Acts of War is a technothriller by Jeff Rovin Plot introduction
The mobile Regional Operations Center (ROC) in Turkey investigates a dam blown up by Kurdish terrorists.
. Chaucer's images also evoke the human anger generated by circumstances, not just by the actions of other human beings: the carter trapped under his cart, the sailor shipwrecked on the sea, and the child threatened in its own cradle figure as prominently as the townspeople whose homes are destroyed by the tyrant tyrant, in ancient history, ruler who gained power by usurping the legal authority. The word is perhaps of Lydian origin and carried with it no connotation of moral censure. . (11) These changes to his source text suggest Chaucer believes that anger, in response to the damage other men do and to the pain God allows the accidents of Fortune to inflict, is both more integral to human affairs and more difficult to contain than Boccaccio does.

In pardoning the knights and constructing the amphitheater, Theseus experiences (and the Knight narrator indulges in) a manner of wish-fulfillment, of the kind we observe in the French fabliau fabliau, plural fabliaux (both: fäblēō`), short comic, often bawdy tale in verse that deals realistically and satirically with middle-class or lower-class characters.  of the Butcher of Abbeville and in the Friar's exemplum ex·em·plum  
n. pl. ex·em·pla
1. An example.

2. A brief story used to make a point in an argument or to illustrate a moral truth.



[Latin; see example.]
 of the widow and the summoner. Theseus can "reject" anger because he has the power to reassert reassert
Verb

1. to state or declare again

2. reassert oneself to become significant or noticeable again: reality had reasserted itself

Verb 1.
 his authority after an affront af·front  
tr.v. af·front·ed, af·front·ing, af·fronts
1. To insult intentionally, especially openly. See Synonyms at offend.

2.
a. To meet defiantly; confront.

b.
 to that authority, as the Butcher of Abbeville has the power, through his vengeful joke, to reassert his pride after it is wounded. That power is limited for most of Chaucer's characters. The anger of the Friar and the Summoner is never resolved entirely because neither has the power Theseus does to impose his will on events and on the community. At the beginning of the Canterbury Tales Chaucer offers us this ideal, but we see throughout the rest of the book its limitations, and the difficulty of applying it in everyday life. And for those who do have such power, the consequences may be less than ideal for everyone else, if we hesitate, as Elizabeth Fowler suggests Chaucer does, to embrace the ethics of Theseus' authoritarian rule by conquest.

The Knight's Tale, like the Prioress' Tale, seems concerned that enfolding en·fold  
tr.v. en·fold·ed, en·fold·ing, en·folds
1. To cover with or as if with folds; envelop.

2. To hold within limits; enclose.

3. To embrace.
 the individual's anger into public justice merely introduces the potential for many more angers to surface, for the angry individual to be replaced by an angry community. In the Prioress' Tale, the escalation and multiplication of anger is more evident, but such expansion lurks at the edges of the Knight's Tale. We see it in the vicarious vicarious /vi·car·i·ous/ (vi-kar´e-us)
1. acting in the place of another or of something else.

2. occurring at an abnormal site.


vi·car·i·ous
adj.
1.
 participation of the audience in the combat of the two knights (which is extended to a hundred more knights on each side), and in the frustration and resentment Theseus' decision inspires in Emily (an individual sacrificed in the interest of public order). Because one anger exists in relation to others, to "conquer" anger as Jill Mann suggests is at best a pyrrhic victory Pyrrhic victory

a too costly victory; “Another such victory and we are lost.” [Rom. Hist.: “Asculum I” in Eggenburger, 30–31]

See : Defeat
. The idea of "conquering" anger is, I argue in the next section, a Thomist ideal critiqued by Chaucer throughout the Knight's Tale.

III. Anger and Change: Thomist Theory of the Passions and the Knight's Tale

Expanding on Mary Carruthers' analysis of the link between architecture and emotional expression in medieval culture, Elizabeth Fowler's study of passion and social discourse in the Knight's Tale observes Chaucer's use of ritual forms to express and to contain the passions of grief, anger, and desire. Chaucer is aware, as Fowler demonstrates, of the relation between the passions and social forms, but also, I think, of the way in which anger in particular resists containment by ritual and social forms. Unlike the scholastic approaches to anger, which look to reason and logic as antidotes for anger, Chaucer's response to the threat posed by anger to human fellowship does not depend merely on rationally crafting the proper social ritual for anger. Instead, Chaucer's narratives feature acceptance of anger as an inevitable part of social life and countenance (even encourage) anger's movement among its many forms.

This interest in the movement and the pervasion per·vade  
tr.v. per·vad·ed, per·vad·ing, per·vades
To be present throughout; permeate. See Synonyms at charge.



[Latin perv
 of anger in human affairs is, I argue, in part what distinguishes Chaucer's treatment of anger from other more scholastic approaches. Aquinas' thoughts on anger serve as a touchstone. Chaucer shares with Aquinas certain basic cultural assumptions about the passions, but his tales depict a different pattern of movement for anger, and thus point to a different way of thinking about the place of anger in human society. (12)

The scholastic tradition assigns a positive value to "rational" anger. The justice of God is tempered with such anger. In hell the pilgrim Dante initially questions the logic of divine anger, but the purpose of his journey is in part to come to an understanding of the nature of God's justice. He learns even to embrace and imitate such anger as he hardens himself against the suffering of sinners. If an individual's rational anger is not satisfied in this world because a sinner goes unpunished unpunished
Adjective

without suffering or resulting in a penalty: the guilty must not go unpunished, such crimes should not remain unpunished

Adj. 1.
, it is because of a flaw in the human justice system, not because the anger is undeserving of justice. (13) Aquinas, too, observes that just anger is not the province of God alone (On Evil q.12, a. 2, reply to 14; and q.12, a. 3, reply to 5). Human anger can be just; it is judged according to according to
prep.
1. As stated or indicated by; on the authority of: according to historians.

2. In keeping with: according to instructions.

3.
 its degree and its motive. For Aquinas, capital punishment capital punishment, imposition of a penalty of death by the state. History


Capital punishment was widely applied in ancient times; it can be found (c.1750 B.C.) in the Code of Hammurabi.
 may be the clearest example of rational anger and its expression; the anger directed at the criminal is an objective one expressed by a legally empowered magistrate on behalf of a community. To avoid the problem inherent in Dante's condemnation of Filippo Argenti Filippo Argenti (13th century), a citizen of Florence, was a member of the Cavicciuoli branch of the Adimari family. The Adimari family were part of the Black Guelph political faction. Filippo is reputed to have received the nickname "Argenti" by having his horse shoed with silver.  (Canto can·to  
n. pl. can·tos
One of the principal divisions of a long poem.



[Italian, from Latin cantus, song; see canticle.
 VIII), in which there is a danger of confusing the individual's sinful anger with objective rational anger, Aquinas tends to emphasize the importance of law and the role of magistrates: anger must avoid seeking "to punish one who does not deserve it, or more than he deserves, or not according to the legitimate process of law" (ST II-II, q. 158, a. 2, resp.). (14) Chaucer's texts, however, sensitive to the individual's claim to his own anger, expose the problem of a doctrine which attempts to limit or to ignore the anger of the average person. Where the scholastic sermon tradition discourages the average individual from expressing anger, Chaucer explores the potential utility of permitting anger--possibly even immoderate im·mod·er·ate  
adj.
Exceeding normal or appropriate bounds; extreme: immoderate spending; immoderate laughter. See Synonyms at excessive.
 and highly subjective or personal anger--to move between average individuals in daily life.

Even in the tales of the Knight, the pilgrim Chaucer, and the Prioress --each of which is largely concerned with the negative impact of anger on the community--Chaucer's poetry runs counter to the principles of scholastic thought on anger. Chaucer's deviation from scholastic writ ers stems, in part, from the fact that Aquinas' writing on anger has its roots in Gregory's metaphor of righteous anger as "the handmaid hand·maid   also hand·maid·en
n.
1. A woman attendant or servant.

2. often handmaiden Something that accompanies or is attendant on another:
" to reason (On Evil q.12, a. 1, resp.).

Aquinas is acutely aware that anger often operates outside the control of reason, contributing to anger's prominent place among the deadly sins. But in Aquinas' logical outline of the nature of anger, as in Aristotle's, there is the assumption that anger can be regulated by reason. The scholastic solution to the problem of anger is to be aware of its potential surfacing and to subject it repeatedly to the pre-emptive analysis of reason; or to attempt to out-think an anger which has surfaced. We hear in Aquinas the confidence of Aristotle, particularly in statements regarding the dissipation of anger. "If vengeance is actually enjoyed, the satisfaction is complete and the distress totally eliminated. This quiets the angry urge [et per hoc quietat motum irae]" (ST I-II q. 48, a. 1, resp.). Over time "the motive for anger is gradually weakened until it is dissipated [Et ideo causa irae per tempus paulatim diminuitur quousque totaliter tollatur]" (ST I-II q. 48, a. 2, ad 2). Anger is, argues Aquinas, a fire which has consumed its materials. Why, he asks, are we are not angry with the dead? Because "they seem already to have met the ultimate evil. This is why we cease to be angry with men who have been seriously injured, with the thought that their misfortune has more than satisfied retributive justice Retributive justice maintains that proportionate punishment is a morally acceptable response to crime, regardless of whether the punishment causes any tangible benefits.

In ethics and law, "Let the punishment fit the crime
" (ST I-II, q. 47, a. 4, ad 2). These ideas derive from the Aristotelian epigrams on anger often quoted by Aquinas: "punishment appeases the thrust of anger, replacing sadness with satisfaction"; and "time quiets anger" (ST I-II, q. 48, a. 1, obj. 2; and ST I-II, q. 48, a. 2, obj. 2).

Aquinas assigns less value than Chaucer to the free movement of anger in society, though the relationship between anger and movement is, from the medieval point of view, a logical one. Aquinas' medieval discourse on the passions, derived from Aristotle, depends on the word motus or mutationus, and describes the effect of a stimulus on the soul in terms of movement or change (ST I-II, q. 22, a. 1-3; and ST I-II, q. 23, a. 2, resp.). Both anger and pity are classified as passions; thus both are indicative of the movements or changes registered by the soul's encounter with a stimulus outside itself. Medieval metaphysics describes the interior movement of anger within the soul (or rather the angry movement of the soul in reaction to an exterior stimulus).

Chaucer presumably pre·sum·a·ble  
adj.
That can be presumed or taken for granted; reasonable as a supposition: presumable causes of the disaster.
 shares his culture's understanding of the relation between anger (the passion) and conceptions of movement and change, though he is more concerned with social and ethical than with metaphysical analysis. The abstractions of interior spiritual motion Chaucer renders with more concrete images of exterior, physical, movement and change; or with pointed images of lack of movement and change as we observed in Theseus' architectural use of the grove. As we will see in the next section, in the episode of the Argive widows Chaucer measures the personal and social effects of anger by changes in behavior, location, or perspective. At the center of Chaucer's vision of the human world is concern for the moral, spiritual, and ethical spaces to which an individual can be transported. His work explores the liminal liminal /lim·i·nal/ (lim´i-n'l) barely perceptible; pertaining to a threshold.

lim·i·nal
adj.
Relating to a threshold.



liminal

barely perceptible; pertaining to a threshold.
 character of anger which tests the ability of the individual and the community to change and to move forward.

As I suggested at the end of the last section, Chaucer depicts anger as a resurfacing force--partly a consequence, I think, of describing the human passions in concrete terms. In the abstractions of metaphysics, the interior movement of the spirit can be imagined to have a definite beginning and an end. Because it is an abstraction, the movement of the "angry" soul is defined by such terminal points. Such points are not always as obvious in Chaucer's narrative descriptions of anger, and it proves more difficult to locate the source or the final effect in his tales. Narrative is especially suitable for Chaucer's exploration of anger because narrative has a potential for irresolution ir·res·o·lute  
adj.
1. Unsure of how to act or proceed; undecided.

2. Lacking in resolution; indecisive.



ir·res
 and uncertainty which Chaucer exploits to express his own ambivalent attitude toward anger. In contrast, the completion and finality fi·nal·i·ty  
n. pl. fi·nal·i·ties
1. The condition or fact of being final.

2. A final, conclusive, or decisive act or utterance.

Noun 1.
 of Aquinas' carefully reasoned propositions of point, counterpoint counterpoint, in music, the art of combining melodies each of which is independent though forming part of a homogeneous texture. The term derives from the Latin for "point against point," meaning note against note in referring to the notation of plainsong. , and synthesis reflect the confident assumption which underpins his analysis--the belief that, whatever the threat posed by anger to human reason, anger can ultimately be subdued or extinguished.

Recent critics have found less reason to be confident of the resolution of events in the Knight's Tale. Barbara Nolan writes:
   Chaucer replaces Boccaccio's Aristotelian system with the less
   optimistic Ciceronian and Senecan system that had, until the
   mid-thirteenth century, typically informed medieval treatises on
   virtue as well as guidebooks for princes. Within this system, the
   moral virtues are specifically intended to counter not their
   opposing vices but the power of 'Fortune and hire false wheel,
   / That noon estaat assureth to be weel' (I.925-26).... [The]
   English poet systematically reworked the character of Boccaccio's
   Teseo, deliberately replacing his Aristotelian virtues
   with the moral virtues outlined in Stoic and pseudo-Stoic
   treatises and with a generally Stoic view of the moral world as
   the domain of Fortune, time, passionate desire, pain, and aventure.
   The battle between the virtues and Fortune in the pagan world of
   the Knight's Tale, unlike the battle between the Aristotelian
   virtues and vices in the Teseida, does not issue in the unequivocal
   triumph of human perfection. While Theseus does achieve a somber,
   rational, social harmony at the end of Chaucer's poem, it is a
   tenuous harmony, always subject to further change, further aventure.
   (250-51)


I have framed my discussion of Chaucer and anger in relation to Aquinas and Dante, more so than in relation to Aristotle and Boccaccio, in part because, among late medieval writers, Aquinas and Dante address the subject of both human and divine anger with as much directness and concern as, I argue, does Chaucer. There is, I think, more to be said about Boccaccio and anger, particularly the relation between narrative and anger in the Decameron (as in the Canterbury Tales), though I am not certain anger is as central a preoccupation for Boccaccio as it is for Chaucer. Nonetheless, whether we speak in terms of Aristotle or Aquinas, Boccaccio or Dante, the point is that Chaucer's work carves a space for itself outside of and in dialogue with the scholastic and Aristotelian tradition. Anger, I argue, is an especially important topic for Chaucer because it attaches itself to the "pessimism" of his world view. The concept of "aventure" itself gives rise to existential anger at a universe organized in this uncertain way (an anger in evidence, I argue below, at the end of the Knight's Tale). And in such a view there can be little confidence that anger can be vanquished.

Chaucer's interest is less in establishing anger as a morally acceptable state, than in understanding the role which anger plays in human communities. Because he is less certain about the power of reason to either prevent or contain anger, he devotes more attention than the scholastic tradition to the presence of anger in human life, and is more willing to consider how to make use of that presence. Moral or not, good for the soul or not, anger is an inevitable part of the human condition and of human society which Chaucer's tales describe. In order to preserve community, Chaucer's characters must engage with anger in order to move it forward. (15) Because anger generally cannot be avoided--either because human beings lack the power of reason or because the power of reason is insufficient--they must risk a liminal moment (becoming immobilized in a state of perpetual anger) if they are to engage with it in a positive way.

IV. Shifting Passions: Pity and Anger in the Opening Sequence of the Knight's Tale

It is in Theseus' encounter with the Argive widows that Chaucer presents us, at the opening of the first of the Canterbury Tales, with an image of such risk:
   This duc, of whom I make mencioun,
   Whan he was come almoost unto the toun,
   In al his wele and in his mooste pride,
   He was war, as he caste his eye aside,
   Where that ther kneled in the heighe weye
   A compaignye of ladyes, tweye and tweye,
   Ech after oother, clad in clothes blake;
   But swich a cry and swich a wo they make
   That in this world nys creature lyvynge
   That herde swich another waymentynge;
   And of this cry they nolde nevere stenten
   Til they the reynes of his brydel henten.
   "What folk been ye, that at myn homcomynge
   Perturben so my feste with criynge?"
   Quod Theseus. "Have ye so greet envye
   Of myn honour, that thus compleyne and crye?
   Or who hath yow mysboden or offended?
   And telleth me if it may been amended,
   And why that ye been clothed thus in blak." (893-911)


Initially, Theseus' actions toward the widows seem again to offer the possibility of successful management and containment of anger. Theseus may be a man of sudden passions, but those shifts in passion are accompanied by shifts in perspective and self-awareness. In a moment, his whole point of view is inverted inverted

reverse in position, direction or order.


inverted L block
a pattern of local filtration anesthesia commonly used in laparotomy in the ox.
. (The "or" at line 909 underscores the either/or character of the divide, his movement from one possible view to another). Initially he asks who the widows are only in relation to his world (to, he says, "myn homcomynge," "myn feste Feste

playful fool. [Br. Lit.: Twelfth Night]

See : Clowns
," "myn honour"), but then his narrative gives way to theirs, and he becomes their audience ("Telleth me").

Such positive change is effected by his willingness to listen to others' stories and, adopting the perspective of the speaker, to be moved by them:
   This gentil duc doun from his courser sterte
   With herte pitous, whan he herde hem speke.
   Hym thoughte that his herte wolde breke,
   Whan he saugh hem so pitous and so maat,
   That whilom weren of so greet estaat;
   And in his armes he hem alle up hente,
   And hem conforteth in ful good entente (952-58)


It is the widows' story, its content and nature, which affects Theseus, but also the very act of listening itself: "whan he herde hem speke." For Chaucer, the act of listening requires a certain curtailing of self-interest, a willingness to move out of one's own perspective. Listening is important because it establishes the initial conditions under which a story is received. It does not, of course, guarantee a reception devoid of anger (as we see in the case of the Friar and Summoner), but it does allow for dialogue, or at least a period in which anger may be suspended.

In addition to the virtue of listening, one can point to more fundamental virtues which contribute to the change in Theseus. David Anderson David Anderson may refer to:
  • David Anderson (Canadian politician) (born 1937), Canadian Liberal politician and former cabinet member
  • David Anderson (bishop) (1814–1885) English Anglican bishop
  • David Anderson (Fictional Character) From
 sees the opening scene with the Argive widows--absent from Statius and not as prominent in Boccaccio--as the product of Chaucer's decision to foreground the virtue of clementia, or mercy (123). Jill Mann explains the change in Theseus in terms of the pietas at the heart of his character, exemplified in his willingness to be open to change:

In the opening episode with widow ladies.... Theseus's openness to 'pitee' was equally an openness to change, a willingness to respond and adapt to 'aventure', the unforeseen and arbitrary interventions of chance. In granting the request of the widow ladies, Theseus abandons his plans for triumph and celebration, allowing their grief to replace his own rejoicings. Having just concluded one war and turned his mind to feasting, he finds he must start all over again, leave his bride, and go to war again. His acceptance of this change in his plans is, as Chaucer emphasizes, total and immediate: he goes not a foot further towards Athens..., and does not rest so much as half a day, but at once sets out for Thebes. This readiness to change, to drop one set of plans and conceptions or attitudes, characterizes Theseus throughout the tale. (Feminizing Chaucer 137-38) (16)

I would agree that the importance of the scene with the widows lies, in part, in its promise of relief and transformation beyond anger. For with the intrusion upon the individual's perspective comes the opportunity for patience and for fellowship. Chaucer sees contained within the disruption itself the possibility of the healing moment when Theseus descends from his horse and embraces the widows--arguably a better man (in ethical and Christian terms) than he was upon his horse, content to be the returning hero-conqueror.

However, thinking about the Knight's Tale as a tale of anger rather than a tale of pity allows us to think further about Chaucer's understanding of the relation between anger and pity, and of the complicated role anger plays in human society. We should observe that anger has a necessary and positive role here, beyond any Stoic claim for "just" anger in a "just" war against Creon. In the scholastic theory of the passions, anger is characterized by an interior movement of the soul. Extreme anger is often negatively associated with the end of physical movement, as the summoner in the Friar's Tale discovers that the logic of divine anger imagines hell as a space beyond which no further movement is possible (Bloomfield). Yet at the opening of the Knight's Tale, though the interruption of the widows puts an end to Theseus' progression toward Athens, it brings too the possibility for new movement. Engaging Theseus' anger actually prevents stagnation Stagnation

A period of little or no growth in the economy. Economic growth of less than 2-3% is considered stagnation. Sometimes used to describe low trading volume or inactive trading in securities.

Notes:
A good example of stagnation was the U.S. economy in the 1970s.
 by creating movement and sending Theseus in a direction which, ethically speaking, is arguably ar·gu·a·ble  
adj.
1. Open to argument: an arguable question, still unresolved.

2. That can be argued plausibly; defensible in argument: three arguable points of law.
 more progressive. Breaking into Theseus' world, risking his anger, is necessary for the widows to be helped and for Theseus to break out of his self-involved celebration.

There is thus a felix-culpa logic to the scene. Perhaps the power of Chaucer's felix-culpa lies in the fact that it is an accessible and easily imagined scene--more so, for example, than the felix-culpa scenario which underpins the trajectory of Christian history from Adam to Christ, or the felix-culpa spirit of Christian eschatology
See also:
In Christian theology, Christian eschatology is the study of its religious beliefs concerning all future and final events (End Times), as well as the ultimate purpose(s) of the world (i.e.
, where death brings life. Theseus' embrace of the widows is a concrete and tangible image of compassion and healing after death. The scene effectively illustrates the possibility of transformation in a human situation, as Chaucer fleshes out the theories of scholastics and preachers without appealing to abstractions alone. And at the heart of that transformative potential, in addition to the virtue of pietas indicative of a willingness to consider alternatives, is a willingness to engage with anger.

If the story of Theseus and the widows ended with the embrace, it would have a satisfying closure, and work well as an exemplum in a sermon on patience (or on felix-culpa theology). But Chaucer's placement of the episode in a larger narrative--while it permits analysis of the episode as an independent scene--does not allow for a self-contained conclusion, not without doing exegetical ex·e·get·ic   also ex·e·get·i·cal
adj.
Of or relating to exegesis; critically explanatory.



ex
 violence to the tale as a whole. Such is the cost of using complex narrative in place of the self-contained abstractions and parables of the philosophical and sermon tradition. Chaucerian narrative often allows for the possibility of such a satisfying ending, but, having highlighted the possibility, generally moves on to imagine other more complicated possibilities which depend on the initial event and extend its consequences. The passage has a larger context and, to do it justice, should be quoted with the lines that follow:
   This gentil duc doun from his courser sterte
   With herte pitous, whan he herde hem speke.
   Hym thoughte that his herte wolde breke,
   Whan he saugh hem so pitous and so maat,
   That whilom weren of so greet estaat;
   And in his armes he hem alle up hente,
   And hem conforteth in ful good entente,
   And swoor his ooth, as he was trewe knyght,
   He wolde doon so ferforthly his myght
   Upon the tiraunt Creon hem to wreke
   That al the peple of Grece sholde speke
   How Creon was of Theseus yserved
   As he that hadde his deeth ful wel deserved. (952-64)


The transition at lines 958-959 makes all the difference: "And hem conforteth in ful good entent, / And swoor his ooth...." Instead of merely comforting the widows, Theseus interprets their supplication as a call for vengeance, and so couples his oath to avenge a·venge  
tr.v. a·venged, a·veng·ing, a·veng·es
1. To inflict a punishment or penalty in return for; revenge: avenge a murder.

2.
 them with the personal sympathy he extends. As in the grove scene, here an anger which seems defeated gives way to a new and more powerful form.

One explanation for such an emotional shift is that the Knight's Tale represents Chaucer's celebration of Stoic virtues, which demand righteous anger from Theseus. Barbara Nolan argues that Chaucer makes a distinction "between Theseus' form of compassionate justice and another less high-minded kind of pitee. This latter, weaker form of pity the widows' bitter tears seem to represent.... But Theseus does not fall into tears. Instead, he prepares himself for action to right a patent wrong." Senecan or Stoic justice, Nolan explains (266, 264), has multiple elements including clementia or misericordia (figured as Theseus' sympathy for the widows) and severitas or vindicatio (figured as Thesefus' just anger and war against Creon).

I am wary of explaining Theseus' anger and the ensuing war only in terms of the Stoic values which permeate permeate /per·me·ate/ (-at?)
1. to penetrate or pass through, as through a filter.

2. the constituents of a solution or suspension that pass through a filter.


per·me·ate
v.
 the tale. Although the Stoic connection between pity, justice, and war does provide us a logical explanation for Theseus' actions, it is notable that Chaucer's economic handling of the transition makes Theseus' movement here seem to be as much about emotion and energy as about logic or rational principles. He immediately turns to Thebes and establishes himself as the principal force of his and his subordinates' destinies. Virtually no "story-time" elapses between the embrace and the beginning of war; the poetry itself fuses the action into a few brief lines. The aggressive energy which seems magically to dissipate dis·si·pate  
v. dis·si·pat·ed, dis·si·pat·ing, dis·si·pates

v.tr.
1. To drive away; disperse.

2.
 in the exchange with the widows, reappears with a vengeance in the war with Thebes. As the amphitheater serves to reconfigure the aggressive energy roused when the knights initially flout flout  
v. flout·ed, flout·ing, flouts

v.tr.
To show contempt for; scorn: flout a law; behavior that flouted convention. See Usage Note at flaunt.

v.intr.
 Theseus' authority, so in a sense does the war provide an outlet for the unvented frustration roused by the widows when they interrupt Theseus' victory march.

Elizabeth Fowler describes this transformation in terms of political and cultural ritual:
   [R]hetorical forms throughout the Knight's Tale provide a lens
   through which the reader can see conflicts between human passions
   and the ceremonies of social life. The contrast between the
   triumph and the lament enacts a breach in decorum that provokes
   Theseus to the ritual of war. Theseus's pity, an apparent index of
   his character's suitability for rule, is quickly converted to
   avenging anger. These passions result in the funeral
   the widows wanted..., but also in the gruesome ransacking and
   pillaging of Thebes. Only when Thebes is leveled does Theseus
   complete his triumph. (61)


Fowler refers here to the "triumph" as the ritual--the formal procession and the attendant celebrations--which expresses joy. The cultural ritual is the "mold," as she says, into which the passions were poured in medieval culture. Funerals are the ritual of grief, and war the ritual of anger. One of Chaucer's goals in the Knight's Tale, she argues, is to explore the sometimes problematic relation between the feelings that the individual experiences and the social forms invented to contain those feelings. One problem with Theseus' triumph, for example, is that it results in considerable lamentation lamentation,
n a prayer expressing affliction or sorrow and requesting defense, retribution, or comfort.
 and woe for Arcite and Palamon (Fowler 66, 61).

Given this essay's interest in movement and in perspective, the concept of "converting" one passion into another is worth pondering. In Fowler's description of the shift from the widow scene to the war scene, pity is "converted" to avenging anger, as one passion (and thus one cultural ritual) supercedes another. The change from one passion to another does not necessarily mean the extinction of another: Theseus' joy is interrupted by pity and anger, though it returns again after the war. The same I would argue is true of his anger, which appears initially when the widows arrest his progress (though it does not last long enough to find expression in a public ritual), and then resurfaces after he sets out for the war against Thebes. The question that Chaucer obscures (deliberately, I think) is whether or not there is a positive ethical connection between the "avenging anger" and the pity from which it is "converted."

On the one hand, one could argue that the quick narrative shift from the pity Theseus displays before the widows to the violence of the Theban war merely reflects a close relation between twin virtues of pietas and righteous anger. For Jill Mann, there is a degree of virtue in the immediacy of Theseus' departure for Thebes: "His acceptance of this change in his plans is, as Chaucer emphasizes, total and immediate: he goes not a foot further towards Athens ..., and does not rest so much as half a day, but at once sets out for Thebes" (Feminizing Chaucer 137):
   And right anoon, withouten moore abood,
   His baner he desplayeth, and forth rood
   To Thebes-ward, and al his hoost biside.
   No neer Atthenes wolde he go ne ride,
   Ne take his ese fully half a day,
   But onward on his wey that nyght he lay,
   And sente anon Ypolita the queene,
   And Emelye, hir yonge suster sheene,
   Unto the toun of Atthenes to dwelle,
   And forth he rit; ther is namoore to telle. (965-74)


For Theseus (as for the Knight) there is "namoore to tell," because Theseus' instant action preempts debate. Ypolita, an Amazon warrior herself, proves to be no Prudence in advising or restraining her husband. Any advice she or Emily might offer (as they do later when he is angry with Palamon and Arcite Palamon and Arcite

victorious jouster (Arcite) dies in fall; loser wins lady’s hand. [Br. Lit.: Canterbury Tales, “Palamon and Arcite”]

See : Last Laugh
) goes unheard because he sends the women to Athens immediately (and "No neer Atthenes wolde he go ne ride"). The Knight takes great pains to underscore Theseus' resolve, presumably because the Knight sees such strength of action as evidence of Theseus being a "trewe knight" (959): "right anoon, withouten moore abood"; "forth rood rood (rd), crucifix mounted above the entrance to the chancel and flanked by large figures of the Virgin and St.  / To Thebe-ward"; "Ne take his ese"; "But Onward"; "And forth he rit." Ten lines are devoted to reiterating Theseus' decision, and there is a heroic feel to his negative statements (he would not rest, he would not go to Athens even for half a day, he would say no more), negating the temptations of rest, of family, of comfort; and to the repetition of his purpose which marks his continued forward movement toward his goal, Thebes.

Yet in the description of Theseus' approach toward Thebes, we find Chaucer undercutting the images of movement and perspective to suggest a disconnect between the Theseus who embraces the widows and the Theseus who assaults Thebes. Although Theseus is constantly moving toward Thebes with each iteration One repetition of a sequence of instructions or events. For example, in a program loop, one iteration is once through the instructions in the loop. See iterative development.

(programming) iteration - Repetition of a sequence of instructions.
 that he chooses to ride rather than hesitate, such physical progress is marked by a lack of formal and imaginative progress. The five couplets make the same basic point again and again, and introduce no new idea because Theseus has no new idea, as he never considers the wisdom or the justness of invading Thebes. So though he makes progress along a linear line in geographical terms, his anger keeps in a static loop as far as reason and imagination are concerned. Distant as Thebes is, he travels no further and makes no greater progress toward defeating his anger than when he later chooses to keep rebuilding upon the same ground within the garden grove Garden Grove, city (1990 pop. 143,050), Orange co., S Calif., a suburb of Long Beach and Los Angeles, on the Santa Ana River; founded 1877, inc. 1956. Many of its residents work in nearby aerospace and defense installations, and there is light manufacturing. . The heroism is evident mainly from within the non-reflective perspective of Theseus himself. From the point of view of the Knight's audience and creator, the Creator, the

common sobriquet for God. [Pop. Usage: Misc.]

See : God
 repetition may seem a little stale, even comic.

With this joke about Theseus' simultaneous progression and lack of progression, Chaucer implies that Theseus, after his encounter with the widows, has changed for the better and yet has not changed. Theseus demonstrates his inclination toward pity, and yet is still driven by anger. That anger is not just the righteous anger converted from the noble pity, as his Stoic principles advise him, but also the anger remaining from having his celebration interrupted. Such anger, as Fowler's discussion intimates, results from the fact that "the contrast between the triumph and the lament enacts a breach in decorum DECORUM. Proper behaviour; good order.
     2. Decorum is requisite in public places, in order to permit all persons to enjoy their rights; for example, decorum is indispensable in church, to enable those assembled, to worship.
 that provokes Theseus to the ritual of war." That it is difficult to untangle these different angers is, I think, Chaucer's point. Anger not only serves many functions but the various angers often become intermingled. This is, I suggest in the next section, a subject which preoccupies Chaucer at the end of the Knight's Tale.

V. Lingering Anger at the End of Knight's Tale: The Failure of Ritual and of Justice

There is one other issue implied by Fowler's description of the passions important to note here. Though each passion--pity, joy, anger--has its ritual, the anger in the widow scene is special in that it results from an interruption of or an insufficiency INSUFFICIENCY. What is not competent; not enough.  of another passion; it is an expression of the failure of other rituals. Again we see that where Aquinas might find resolution, Chaucer introduces instability and continuation. The seizure of Theseus' bridle--this first disruption in the first of the Canterbury Tales--is a moment to bracket. It illustrates the type of situation which so often disturbs characters and pilgrims in Chaucer's work--the breaking in of the universe upon the individual, an interruption of perspective, assumption, hope, ambition, or feeling which angers the individual who believes he has achieved some measure of stability.

This kind of frustration, what we might call existential anger, surfaces again at the end of the Knight's Tale, and characterizes a Chaucerian world beyond the reach of Aquinas' logic. That Aquinas assumes anger can be dissipated is significant, as it allows him to make a distinction between anger which recedes and hatred which persists: "Anger seeks evil only by way of just revenge; when the evil inflicted exceeds the measure of justice, as he sees it, the angry man [unlike the hateful hate·ful  
adj.
1. Eliciting or deserving hatred.

2. Feeling or showing hatred; malevolent.



hateful·ly adv.
 man] will relent re·lent  
v. re·lent·ed, re·lent·ing, re·lents

v.intr.
To become more lenient, compassionate, or forgiving. See Synonyms at yield.

v.tr. Obsolete
1.
" (ST I-II, q. 46, a. 6, ad 1). This distinction by Aquinas is most relevant to the tales of the Prioress and the Man of Law, which seem to broach broach (broch) a fine barbed instrument for dressing a tooth canal or extracting the pulp.

broach
n.
A dental instrument for removing the pulp of a tooth or exploring its canal.
 the issue of cultural hatred. But with respect to Theseus in the Knight's Tale, and to Chaucer's angry characters in general, the distinction is important because it compels us to consider whether Chaucer's angry characters, when their anger does abate, have in fact found justice "as they see it." Aquinas confidently suggests anger finds resolution in justice, but the Knight's Tale establishes right at the outset of the Canterbury project that Chaucer is less certain that the forms of justice his characters find will in fact extinguish Extinguish

Retire or pay off debt.
 their anger.

The prospect that Theseus' justice involves a wholly rational anger--an anger which will obey the boundaries established by an individual or a community seeking Aquinas' rational justness--dissolves when we consider the narrative outcome of Theseus' solution. Even if we find his administration of justice to be both rational and just, we discover that events in the amphitheater expose the community to further kinds of anger. For all the success of the amphitheater in subjecting the heretofore unrestrained private angers of the two knights to the legal and social boundaries of a community, the tournament also proves a reminder of the limits of that human work. For it is not so much that the amphitheater fails initially to contain private anger, but that unforeseen consequences undermine its work and result in the eruption of a different kind of anger: perhaps the most powerful and pervasive in the tale, the anger felt by the whole community upon the death of Arcite.

The consequence of Theseus' administration of justice is a near apocalyptic combination of grief and anger:
   How [the trees] weren feld shal nat be toold for me;
   Ne hou the goddes ronnen up and doun,
   Disherited of hire habitacioun,
   In which the woneden in reste and pees,
   Nymphes, fawnes and amadrides;

   Ne hou the beestes and the briddes alle
   Fledden for fere, whan the wode was falle;
   Ne how the ground agast was of the light,
   That was nat wont to seen the sonne bright;
   Ne how the fyr was couched first with stree,
   And thanne with drye stikkes cloven a thre,
   And thanne with grene wode and spicerye,
   And thanne with clooth of gold and with perrye,
   And gerlandes, hangynge with ful many a flour,
   The mirre, the'encens, with al so greet odour;
   ....

   Ne what jeweles men in the fyre caste,
   Whan that the fyr was greet and brente faste;
   Ne how somme caste hir sheeld, and sommme hir spere,
   And of hire vestimentz, whiche that they were,
   And coppes fulle of wyn, and milk, and blood,
   Into the fyr, that brente as it were wood. (2920-50)


Shrieking and howling (2817)--less grief-specific than wailing and crying --are accompanied by a "Cracchynge of chekes, rentynge eek of heer" (2834), amid a general query of "why." Religion and philosophy tell the people they should not be angry, but there is a furious undercurrent to the woe of Theseus and his people. The funeral pile a structure of combustible material, upon which a dead body is placed to be reduced to ashes, as part of a funeral rite; a pyre.

See also: Funeral
 is not just woeful woe·ful also wo·ful  
adj.
1. Affected by or full of woe; mournful.

2. Causing or involving woe.

3. Deplorably bad or wretched:
, but destructive, adding the (potentially fatal) distress of homeless nymphs and forest animals to Arcite's death. With the cause appearing to be an unassailable target--chance, the humour of Pluto himself--the community's anger is displaced onto assailable targets, and the fires of bereavement Bereavement Definition

Bereavement refers to the period of mourning and grief following the death of a beloved person or animal. The English word bereavement
 rage as the mourners would, if they could.

In Chaucer's description of the conflagration we find a world tearing itself apart. Trees as high as heaven are felled as if in place of heaven itself (2915), leaving the gods homeless (2926)--not, notably, the gods responsible for events, but the spirits of the wood, who are consumed as unrest spreads outward from individuals to the community of Athens and even to the ground itself. The names of sacrificed trees are preserved in a casualty list of great length (2920-24). "And coppes fulle of wyn, and milk, and blood, / Into the fyr, that brente as it were wood": the fire burns all objects as if they were wood--or as if it were itself "wood" (in the secondary medieval sense of the word), a creature of madness and anger incarnate in·car·nate  
adj.
1.
a. Invested with bodily nature and form: an incarnate spirit.

b. Embodied in human form; personified: a villain who is evil incarnate.
. As in the amphitheater, state-sanctioned emotion and the rational state-controlled release of such emotion provide a measure of order and containment, but the excess of the Athenian rites reveals the failure on the part of reason and of a community to subdue sub·due  
tr.v. sub·dued, sub·du·ing, sub·dues
1. To conquer and subjugate; vanquish. See Synonyms at defeat.

2. To quiet or bring under control by physical force or persuasion; make tractable.

3.
 completely a people's anger. Where Aquinas imagines a justice which will dispel such anger, Chaucer questions whether there are any right circumstances in which the anger could be quelled completely.

In the cathartic cathartic (kəthär`tĭk): see laxative.  destruction of goods--vials, weapons, armor, trees--the Athenians take comfort in ritual, but also in the release of energy both mournful mourn·ful  
adj.
1. Feeling or expressing sorrow or grief; sorrowful.

2. Causing or suggesting sadness or melancholy: the mournful sound of a train whistle.
 and hostile. This mourning period and its rites satisfy the people's grief: "By processe and by lenghte of certeyn yeres, / Al stynted is the moornynge and the teres teres /te·res/ (te´rez) [L.] long and round.

te·res
adj.
Being round and long. Used of certain muscles and ligaments.



teres

[L.] long and round.
" (2967-68). Time is a "processe" that heals wounds, dampens passion, or at least makes them seem to lose significance. And, in Chaucerian fashion, the citizens find relief in "pley" (2964), in this particular case "wake-pleyes" (2960) or funeral sporting games in the dead knight's honor. But if grief dissipates, there is reason to expect that anger will exist beyond "the moornynge and the teres" because there is always more death, more frustration. Theseus' remarks suggest that anger with god and the universe is not a sudden passion which rises and burns out, but is a continual struggle.

Whatever the other angers, this anger with death is at the root of life as it is illustrated in Chaucer's tales. Theseus' speech is powerful and has the potential for consolation: "The contrarie of al this is wilfulnesse/ Why grucchen we, why have we hevynesse" (3057-58). Complaint and sorrow, resistance and sadness, anger and grief are regarded as futile pairings. But the Knight's Tale fails to realize all the implications of Boethius' Christianized Stoicism Stoicism (stō`ĭsĭzəm), school of philosophy founded by Zeno of Citium (in Cyprus) c.300 B.C. The first Stoics were so called because they met in the Stoa Poecile [Gr. . (17) In Theseus' acknowledgement of the order--and the constraint--of the divine scheme, there is Stoic acceptance that anger would be pointless. But this does not mean anger dissipates, especially without the Boethian consolation of a divine perspective. Despite Theseus' Stoic reasoning, people do complain, hence the need for the reasoning. There is a hint of bitterness in Theseus' unexpectedly harsh description of life and of the contrast between Arcite's fate and his own (for while Arcite is a dead man, Theseus is a man who has to live with the effect of death in the world): "That goode Arcite, of chivalrie four, / Departed is with duetee and honour / Out of this foule prisoun of this lyf" (3057-3061). All of which makes his parting wish for Palamon and Emily--"parfit joye, lastynge evermo"--seem hollow. Equally hollow is his thanks to Jupiter for his "grace," for making the universe as it is (3069).

In some ways Theseus performs an admirable, if paradoxical, leap of faith, offering obedience where heavenly reward is absent. If his pagan Stoicism falls short, failing to take into account God's sympathy with human suffering, perhaps it makes Christianity more appealing. But I argue that the anger which lingers at the end of the tale is important because the pagan leap of faith is in many ways similar to the Christian's. Both solutions demand great imaginative acts and neither is easy. Boethius may provide a measure of consolation, but he never suggests the achievement of consolation is simple. Chaucer, like Boethius, is sensitive to this problem of imagination. Though we are meant to see that Theseus' solution is incomplete, he nonetheless expresses many of the deep concerns a Christian would have with the universe and its organization (the existence of hell, for example).

On the positive side, the very incompletion and frustration of Theseus' solution may render him that much more accessible to the reader and strengthen his claim as a model Chaucerian character. One reason Custance, Griselda, and Chaucer's other ideal female characters are so remarkable, inspiring wonder in those around them, may be that they almost seem without imagination, or rather, without the need for it. They exist in a world of acceptance beyond anger, making our imaginative involvement with them (our imitation of them or adoption of their perspective) that much more frustrating frus·trate  
tr.v. frus·trat·ed, frus·trat·ing, frus·trates
1.
a. To prevent from accomplishing a purpose or fulfilling a desire; thwart:
 and difficult. While we see the limits of Theseus' imagination, it is important to note that Chaucer also reveals that imagination does help Theseus subdue his anger to a point, and he proves a more human character than Custance or Griselda, and his strategies that much more accessible. His story is in one sense a story about the power of the imagination to shift perspective and contain anger, even as it fails to imagine a world which has exiled anger altogether.

As one modern translator of Aquinas observes, our difficulty engaging imaginatively with medieval discourse on the emotional life of human beings stems in part from the alien quality of the intellectual world medieval writers inhabited:
   For the problem is more than a matter of vocabulary [concerning the
   emotions]: man's self-awareness, and his insight into his own
   passional emotional life, have deepened and sharpened enormously
   since the thirteenth century.... We stand on the shoulders of
   Shakespeare and Rousseau and Dostoievsky; St. Thomas wrote before
   Renaissance Humanism was born. To compare the depth and
   self-awareness of man's passional and emotional life evidenced in
   the medieval lyrics and romances with that of the Shakespearian
   tragedies and problem plays is a little like comparing the
   anatomical knowledge of trecento painters with that of
   Michelangelo. (18)


Yet in Chaucer, at least in his treatment of anger, we see a precursor of this modern shift. His writings evince e·vince  
tr.v. e·vinced, e·vinc·ing, e·vinc·es
To show or demonstrate clearly; manifest: evince distaste by grimacing.
 a burgeoning awareness that anger presents a greater psychological complexity and travels a more unpredictable path than the scholastic analysis prepares for. For Chaucer, immoderate anger is not merely a failure of reason, and justice is not the simple antidote it may seem in the abstract examples of scholastic thought, where the passions have an identifiable exterior agent and those agents can be rationally managed. The hope that justice will erase anger presents a problem when justice--as it is defined by the law, by custom, or by God--proves unsatisfactory. Divine justice is by definition just, but it is not necessarily a remedy for human anger, any more than, say, personal revenge is. Chaucer's identification with a deep-rooted anger towards the way the universe is organized sets his work apart from the scholastics. The distinction is thus not necessarily between a medieval as opposed to a Renaissance or "modern" conception of anger. It is more of a distinction between those who have made their peace with God by accepting the principle of justice and those who have not. As Prudence dis covers she must advise Melibee, "aboven alle thynges ... make pees bitwene God and yow yow  
interj.
Used to express alarm, pain, or surprise.
, / and beth reconciled unto hym and to his grace" (1713-14). In Theseus, in the first of the Canterbury Tales, we find the first embodiment of the Chaucerian character who struggles with the burden of making his peace with God.

Notes

(1) All citations from the Canterbury Tales refer to The Riverside Chaucer. Ed. Larry D. Benson. 3rd ed. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Houghton Mifflin Company is a leading educational publisher in the United States. The company's headquarters is located in Boston's Back Bay. It publishes textbooks, instructional technology materials, assessments, reference works, and fiction and non-fiction for both young readers , 1987.

(2) Mann, of course, is sensitive to the important role anger plays in many of the tales; her article on anger and "glosynge" provides a useful outline of the topic, particularly of the function of anger within the "marriage" group ("Anger and 'Glosynge' in the Canterbury Tales"). It is notable, however, that this material is largely absent from her discussion of Chaucer's ethics in Feminizing Chaucer. Though references to anger inevitably surface in discussions of patience (in reference to Theseus for example [136]), anger is not a topic that ever rises to the level of a subject, failing to garner a place in the chapter titles or the index--understandably so, given that the ideal characters Mann is most interested in rarely display anger themselves and generally offer alternatives to their male counterparts. An identification of Chaucer's ethical vision with the "feminine" virtues of patience and mercy would seem to push the issue of anger to the margins, or relegate rel·e·gate  
tr.v. rel·e·gat·ed, rel·e·gat·ing, rel·e·gates
1. To assign to an obscure place, position, or condition.

2. To assign to a particular class or category; classify. See Synonyms at commit.
 it to a well-defined role as the enemy of patience, to be mastered with aide from her sister, mercy.

(3) As Patterson explicates: "The heroic Theseus artifex is here represented by John the Carpenter, his astrological as·trol·o·gy  
n.
1. The study of the positions and aspects of celestial bodies in the belief that they have an influence on the course of natural earthly occurrences and human affairs.

2. Obsolete Astronomy.
 credulity cre·du·li·ty  
n.
A disposition to believe too readily.



[Middle English credulite, from Old French, from Latin cr
 inciting him, to his cost, to pry into 'Goddes pryvetee' (3454, 3558), just as Theseus's hubristic oratiories invoked planetary gods who then brought disasters down upon the world that worshipped them. In its largest sense, the Tale teaches a lesson about the impossibility of constraining either people or events to the kind of overmastering that characterizes chivalry" (131).

(4) Aers shares the Miller's skepticism of Theseus' wisdom: "[Chaucer] exposes the poem to the reactions of both 'gentils' and class-conscious miller within his fiction, developing a literary form which will constantly resist attempts at closure of any kind. Far from being a text which exalts Theseus, his practices or his ideas, Chaucer's poem encourages our imagination and intellect to penetrate and supersede To obliterate, replace, make void, or useless.

Supersede means to take the place of, as by reason of superior worth or right. A recently enacted statute that repeals an older law is said to supersede the prior legislation.
 the forms of language and life represented by the duke and his order" (194).

(5) As Pratt elucidates: "Chaucer's decision to retain Boccaccio's Theban war references.... reflects another universal notion. Wars sometimes have to be fought.... The war against Thebes takes place not because the gods want it out of some whim, but because Theseus sees a need to redress a wrong. Thebes is a dangerous city ... . Thus, the war against Thebes represents order versus chaos; Theseus stands for order (what medieval intellectuals called securitas" (180).

(6) There is, as Fowler argues, a problem with apolitical a·po·lit·i·cal  
adj.
1. Having no interest in or association with politics.

2. Having no political relevance or importance: claimed that the President's upcoming trip was purely apolitical.
 or ahistorical a·his·tor·i·cal  
adj.
Unconcerned with or unrelated to history, historical development, or tradition: "All of this is totally ahistorical.
 criticism that mires itself in the question of whether Theseus is, ethically speaking, a "good or bad" individual:
   There is nothing wrong with benevolence, but benevolence is
   insufficient for good rule.... The task that Chaucer sets the
   reader is ... not to decide whether Theseus's character is good
   or bad ... but rather it is to question whether conquest can be
   compatible with good governance.... An ethical evaluation of
   Theseus must be complemented by a political one. (65)


This seems to me an important caveat with respect to the treatment of anger in the tale, in the sense that Chaucer is interested in both the containment of anger and the political consequences of the methods of containment. Even if we determine that Theseus achieves a measure of stability for both himself and his community, we need not conclude that his strategies of anger management come without cost, personal or political. On the whole, however, my essay on anger and society takes Theseus out of the context of these political and genre analyses, in order to focus on the way in which anger (rather than politics or the chivalric chi·val·ric  
adj.
Of or relating to chivalry.

Adj. 1. chivalric - characteristic of the time of chivalry and knighthood in the Middle Ages; "chivalric rites"; "the knightly years"
knightly, medieval
 code) influences events in Theseus' life and in the life of the Athenian community. When we regard the tale as a tale of anger, we see that it has application beyond the political world, with Theseus serving as an example of how any individual can be pulled in multiple directions by his anger, and of how certain kinds of anger can diffuse through whole communities irrespective of irrespective of
prep.
Without consideration of; regardless of.

irrespective of
preposition despite 
 social position or occupation.

(7) It is in reference to this scene that Jill Mann writes of Theseus' willingness to "combat" anger and of his ability to "conquer" it. That Chaucer's invests his Theseus with a more forceful and extended anger than Boccaccio's Teseo is, Mann suggests, part of Chaucer's plan to illustrate the extent and the nature of Theseus' virtue:

Theseus's 'ire', though rejected, nevertheless plays an essential role in this scene.... Theseus's anger shows, first of all, that his capacity for 'pitee' is not the result of a constitutional lethargy or softness; the 'pitous' hero is as fiery and peremptory peremptory adj. absolute, final and not entitled to delay or reconsideration. The term is applied to writs, juror challenges or a date set for hearing.


PEREMPTORY. Absolute; positive. A final determination to act without hope of renewing or altering.
 as other men. But even more important, it shows the dynamic power of 'pitee', its capacity to effect change. The importance of showing us Theseus as first violently angry, and then yielding to pity, is that it shows us Theseus changing his mind along with his mood. 'Pitee', that is, represents not only a willingness to sympathize and forgive, it also represents an openness to change--change of heart, change of plans. (Mann, Feminizing Chaucer 136-37)

For a dissenting view, see Olsson 125. Olsson sees Theseus' pity for the knights as a serious error in judgement and Theseus as a character of limited wisdom, "by his 'pity' dooming both characters to greater wretchedness."

(8) My rethinking of Mann's vision of Theseus as a successful manager of anger has been influenced, in part, by the work Mary Carruthers and Elizabeth Fowler have done in identifying Chaucer's interest in the relation between human passions and the specific linguistic and social forms invented in response to them. As Fowler suggests, by commissioning the amphitheater Theseus creates a new ritual to empower himself and, I would add, to channel the anger after his authority has been challenged by the illegal duel.

(9) Mary Carruthers observes the way in which architecture serves as a mnemonic Pronounced "ni-mon-ic." A memory aid. In programming, it is a name assigned to a machine function. For example, COM1 is the mnemonic assigned to serial port #1 on a PC. Programming languages are almost entirely mnemonics.  aide to the reader and the way in which Chaucer invests certain locations with specific emotional significance:
   Each has a distinguishing sound or melody (or hushed silence)
   associated with it that summons up a primary emotion (woe,
   lust, anger, courage, awe), and each serves the nexus of the
   tale's matters; recalled in order, they summarize the things
   in the Knight's tale that are worth remembering. (102)


If we posit this deep structural connection between emotion and physical space, anger appears to be an especially important element of the tale. The grove in which the two knights duel is a central space in the tale; Carruthers observes that Chaucer (unlike Boccaccio, who places the temples in different places around the city) concentrates information in the space of the amphitheater, which is built upon the dueling grove and will later serve as the setting for the funeral pyre (Carruthers 105).

(10) Chaucer, I think, uses the reinvention of this space, and the re-ignition of anger after each refashioning, as an image of cosmetic change without movement--a Chaucerian metaphor, as it were, for human anger that resurfaces in different forms but in the same spaces when individuals only appear to have conquered anger by changing or by moving on.

(11) Boccaccio's description of the Temple of Mars is shorter than Chaucer's, and tends to be both more abstract and more focused on the consequences of tyranny and war:
   It seemed to her [Arcite's prayer] that she saw mad Impulses
   coming forth proudly through the door; and Blind Sin and every
   Alas! appeared there too. Wrath, red as fire, and pale Fear were
   also to be seen in that place.

   And she saw Betrayals with their secret weapons, and Intrigues
   with their fair appearance. Discord was seated there, holding
   bloody weapons and every Difference in her hand. All the rooms
   seemed clamorous with harsh Threats and Cruel Design. And in their
   midst sat unhappy Valor, the least to merit praise.

   Merry Madness she saw there as well, and behind him, armed Death
   with his bloody looks, and Bewilderment. Every alter there was
   covered with blood that had been shed by human bodies only in
   battles. Every altar was luminous with the fire taken from
   flame-ravaged lands destroyed by wretched wars.

   And the Temple was all storied by a clever hand, above and
   roundabout. The first scenes pictured there were the depredations
   made day and night on ravished lands. And anyone ever subjected
   to violence was here in somber garb. Enchained peoples, iron
   gates, and demolished fortresses could be seen here.

   She also saw warlike ships there, and empty wagons and ravaged
   countenances, and weeping and unhappy wretches and all Coercions,
   each with arrogant mien. Every wound was visible there, and blood,
   mixed with clay. And turbulent, haughty Mars with his proud
   bearing appeared everywhere. Boccaccio, The Book of Theseus
   [Teseida delle Nozze d'Emilia], VII.33-37.


Chaucer's change to Boccaccio's image of the empty wagon is just one of the many small, but telling, alterations which illustrate Chaucer's different approach to the imagery of Mars. The wagon left abandoned in the face of an invading army is transformed by Chaucer into the carter trapped under his own cart, an image of individual human pain and frustration with circumstances whose cause is unknown and whose remedy is beyond any human being.

(12) Chaucer's narratives focus on the consequence of human anger for individuals and for human society to a greater degree than the writings of Aquinas, which tend to focus on how to define rational anger in the abstract. Like Dante's work, Chaucer's texts evince a deep concern about the social ramifications ramifications nplAuswirkungen pl  of anger (including acts of vengeance Acts of Vengeance is a Marvel Comics 1989-1990 crossover event. Although almost every Marvel Universe series published during that time was involved, the main plot ran through the Avengers comics and was only occasionally referenced elsewhere. ) which threaten to destabilize de·sta·bi·lize  
tr.v. de·sta·bi·lized, de·sta·bi·liz·ing, de·sta·bi·liz·es
1. To upset the stability or smooth functioning of:
 a society. Of course, set in the human world, the Tales approach the problem of anger and society in a different way than Dante's Inferno, which uses an other-worldly setting to reflect on the problems of this world. Dante's pilgrim must come to terms with the violence of divine anger and consider the tricky issue of how the management of anger in the afterlife can serve as a model for better managing anger in human society.

(13) Of course, the treatment of anger in the Inferno is quite complicated, especially the moments where the human anger of the individual confronts the anger of God. For the pilgrim Dante is at once the spokesman for the divine and yet aware of the human perspective which has difficulty incorporating the precepts of divine anger. He is overcome with pity when hearing the tale of Francesca and her monologue decrying God's justice. But by the end of his journey he tends to side with the Thomist anti-Senecan tradition and acknowledges God's just anger. As J. Stephen Russell
:For the Taoist practitioner, see The Barefoot Doctor.|


Stephen Russell is a voice actor, most known for his voice acting in the Thief game series as the protagonist Garrett.
 observes (200), the assumption that Virgil, in encouraging Dante's anger with the sinners in Hell, speaks for God and the Church is a traditional reading of anger in the Inferno, beginning with Borgese's 1938 Speculum article on "The Wrath of Dante" and continuing through Singleton's translation. Russell's counter-argument is provocative. Focusing on the bitter exchange between Dante and Filippo Argenti in Canto VIII, Russell tries to show that "Dante's angry reaction to Argenti is morally questionable, an example of the sin of ira.... something less excellent than, say, the righteous anger of Jesus in the Temple (with which it is sometimes compared)" (200-201). He suggests, too, that Virgil represents a pagan attitude toward anger which encourages the individual to direct his anger with another person's transgressive act at that individual, in direct contradiction of Augustine and Ambrose's call for separation of anger with the sin and anger with the sinner. Ultimately, Russell's argument fails to overturn Borgese's more conservative reading, which is in the background of my argument here. Dante's encounter with Argenti is important because the anger displayed suggests that Dante the pilgrim is learning. The anger he displays is far more appropriate to Hell than the pity he displays in Canto V for Francesca. Still, Russell's questioning of how to interpret Dante's anger reminds us of how difficult it is to evaluate anger, a problem that preoccupies Chaucer's texts: how can one separate anger with the sin from anger with the man? how can the individual properly exercise the just anger of God?

(14) See also On Evil q. 12, art. 3, reply to 5: "For He committed the taking of revenge for public sins to others who are constituted to positions of authority, for in the Epistle to the Romans (3,14) it is said of the man possessing authority that he is 'an avenger of God to execute wrath on him who does evil'...."

(15) Anger persists and so creates change, but within that larger frame of instability, there is potential benefit to the community. The (angry) movement forward is better than the silent rage which isolates individuals, threatening to end fellowship--as we see at the end of the Pardoner's Tale where the unspeakable anger of the Pardoner par·don·er  
n.
1. One that pardons: a pardoner of the sins of others.

2. A medieval ecclesiastic authorized to raise money for religious works by granting papal indulgences to contributors.
 (956-57) and the Host's threat to stop playing (958-59) nearly bring an end the tale-telling game (and thus the pilgrimage itself). And as we will observe in the next section, in the case of the Argive widows, provoking Theseus' anger destabilizes his world but in a potentially beneficial way.

(16) See Burnley 25 for his analysis of the widow scene in the relation to the Ricardian virtue of patience, and 27 for his related discussion of the grove scene.

(17) On the failure of Theseus' Stoicism to approach Boethian consolation, see Kempton 246-47. Also Nolan 280-81.

(18) See pages xx-xxi of Eric D'Arcy's introduction to vol.19 of the Summa.

Works Cited

Aers, David. Chaucer, Langland, and the Creative Imagination. London: Routledge, 1980.

Anderson, David. "The Fourth Temple of the Knight's Tale: Athenian Clemency Leniency or mercy. A power given to a public official, such as a governor or the president, to in some way lower or moderate the harshness of punishment imposed upon a prisoner.

Clemency is considered to be an act of grace.
 and Chaucer's Theseus." Studies in the Age of Chaucer, Proceedings 2 (1986): 113-25.

Aquinas, Thomas. On Evil. Trans. Jean Oesterle. Notre Dame Notre Dame IPA: [nɔtʁ dam] is French for Our Lady, referring to the Virgin Mary. In the United States of America, Notre Dame : U of Notre Dame P, 1995.

--. Summa Theologiae The title Summa Theologiae (or, in some cases, Summa Theologica) refers to several different theological works:
  1. Summa Theologica by Sanctus Antoninus
  2. Summa Theologica by Thomas Aquinas
  3. Summa Theologiae by Alberto Magno
. New York New York, state, United States
New York, Middle Atlantic state of the United States. It is bordered by Vermont, Massachusetts, Connecticut, and the Atlantic Ocean (E), New Jersey and Pennsylvania (S), Lakes Erie and Ontario and the Canadian province of
: McGraw-Hill, 1967. Bloomfield, Morton. "The Friar's Tale as a Liminal Tale." Chaucer Review 17 (1983): 286-91.

Boccaccio, Giovanni Boccaccio, Giovanni (jōvän`nē), 1313–75, Italian poet and storyteller, author of the Decameron. Born in Paris, the illegitimate son of a Tuscan merchant and a French woman, he was educated at Certaldo and Naples by his . The Book of Theseus [Teseida delle Nozze d'Emilia]. Trans. Bernadette Marie McCoy. New York: Medieval Text Association, 1974.

Borgese, G.A. "The Wrath of Dante." Speculum 13 (1938): 183-93.

Burnley, J.D. Chaucer's Language and the Philosophers' Tradition. Cambridge, Eng.: Brewer, 1979.

Carruthers, Mary. "Seeing Things Seeing Things may refer to:
  • Hallucinations where someone sees things that are not actually present
  • Seeing Things (poetry), a collection of poems published by Seamus Heaney in 1991.
  • Seeing Things (TV series), a Canadian television series which aired in the 1980s.
: Locational Memory in Chaucer's Knight's Tale." Art and Context in Late Medieval English Narrative: Essays in Honour of Robert Worth Frank, Jr. Ed. Robert R. Edwards. Cambridge, Eng.: Brewer, 1994. 93-106.

Chaucer, Geoffrey. The Riverside Chaucer. Ed. Larry D. Benson. 3rd ed. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1987.

Dante Alighieri Dante Alighieri (dăn`tē, Ital. dän`tā älēgyĕ`rē), 1265–1321, Italian poet, b. Florence. Dante was the author of the Divine Comedy, one of the greatest of literary classics. . The Inferno. Ed. Charles S. Singleton. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1970.

Fowler, Elizabeth. "The Afterlife of the Civil Dead: Conquest in The Knight's Tale." Critical Essays on Geoffrey Chaucer. Ed. Thomas C. Stillinger. New York: G.K. Hall, 1998. 59-81.

Kempton, Daniel. "Chaucer's Knight and the Knight's Theseus." Journal of Narrative Technique 17 (1987): 237-58.

Mann, Jill. "Anger and 'Glosynge' in the Canterbury Tales." Proceedings of the British Academy The British Academy is the United Kingdom's national academy for the humanities and the social sciences. It was established by Royal Charter in 1902, and is a fellowship of more than 800 scholars. The Academy is self-governing and independent.  1990: 203-23.

--. Feminizing Chaucer. Cambridge, Eng.: Brewer, 2002. Minnis, A.J. Chaucer and Pagan Antiquity. Cambridge, Eng.: Brewer, 1982.

Nolan, Barbara. Chaucer and the Tradition of the Roman Antique. Cambridge, Eng.: Cambridge UP, 1992.

Olsson, Kurt. "Securitas and Chaucer's Knight." Studies in the Age of Chaucer 9 (1987): 123-53.

Patterson, Lee. "'No Man His Reson Herde': Peasant Consciousness, Chaucer's Miller, and the Structure of the Canterbury Tales." Literary Practice and Social Change in Britain, 1380-1530. Ed. Patterson. Berkeley: U of California P, 1990. 113-55.

Pratt, John H. Chaucer and War. Lanham, MD: UP of America, 2000.

Russell, J. Stephen. "Inferno VIII: Dante's Anger and the Sins of Misreading MISREADING, contracts. When a deed is read falsely to an illiterate or blind man, who is a party to it, such false reading amounts to a fraud, because the contract never had the assent of both parties. 5 Co. 19; 6 East, R. 309; Dane's Ab. c. 86, a, 3, Sec. 7; 2 John. R. 404; 12 John. R. ." Literary and Historical Perspectives of the Middle Ages. Ed. Patricia Cummins. Morgantown: West Virginia West Virginia, E central state of the United States. It is bordered by Pennsylvania and Maryland (N), Virginia (E and S), and Kentucky and, across the Ohio R., Ohio (W). Facts and Figures


Area, 24,181 sq mi (62,629 sq km). Pop.
 UP, 1982. 200-07.
COPYRIGHT 2008 Fu Jen University, College of Foreign Languages & Literatures (Fu Jen Ta Hsueh)
No portion of this article can be reproduced without the express written permission from the copyright holder.
Copyright 2008 Gale, Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

 Reader Opinion

Title:

Comment:



 

Article Details
Printer friendly Cite/link Email Feedback
Author:Griffith, John Lance
Publication:Fu Jen Studies: literature & linguistics
Article Type:Critical essay
Geographic Code:1USA
Date:Jan 1, 2008
Words:12831
Previous Article:Full chairs and empty spaces: a kind of entertainment (a record of the translation of Leung Ping-Kwan's "Fourteen Chairs").
Next Article:Narrating Chinese m/others: new orientalism in Amy Tan's The Joy Luck Club.
Topics:

Terms of use | Copyright © 2014 Farlex, Inc. | Feedback | For webmasters